South Africa: Constitutional Court

You are here:
SAFLII >>
Databases >>
South Africa: Constitutional Court >>
1997 >>
[1997] ZACC 11
| Noteup
| LawCite
S v Lawrence , S v Negal ; S v Solberg (CCT38/96, CCT39/96, CCT40/96) [1997] ZACC 11; 1997 (10) BCLR 1348; 1997 (4) SA 1176 (6 October 1997)
Download original files | Links to summary |
CONSTITUTIONAL COURT OF SOUTH AFRICA
Cases CCT 38/96
CCT 39/96
CCT 40/96
REBECCA LAWRENCE Appellant in CCT 38/96
RODNEY GORDON NEGAL
Appellant in CCT 39/96
MAGDALENA PETRONELLA SOLBERG Appellant in CCT
40/96
versus
THE STATE First Respondent
THE
MINISTER OF TRADE AND INDUSTRY Second Respondent
Heard on : 6 May 1997
Decided on : 6 October 1997
JUDGMENT
CHASKALSON P:
The constitutional issues on
appeal
[1] The three appellants were each charged in a
Magistrates’ Court and convicted of contraventions of the Liquor Act 27 of
1989
(“the Liquor Act”). The appellants, all employees of the Seven
Eleven chain store, did not dispute the facts relied
upon by the state at their
trials. They were charged separately and the defence in each case was that the
particular provisions
of the Liquor Act under which that appellant was charged
were inconsistent with the interim
Constitution[1] and were accordingly
invalid.
[2] Each of the cases was concerned with a contravention of the
terms of the grocer’s wine licence authorising the sale of wine
at the
stores at which the appellants were employed. In terms of the Liquor Act the
holder of a grocer’s wine licence is prohibited
from selling liquor other
than table wine.[2] There are also
restrictions on the hours and days on which sales may be
effected.[3] The state’s case
against Ms Lawrence was that she sold wine at a Seven Eleven store during a week
day but after closing hours;
the case against Ms Solberg was that she sold wine
at a Seven Eleven store on a Sunday, which is a closed day for sales of wine by
holders of grocers’ wine licences; and the case against Mr Negal was that
he sold cider and beer at a Seven Eleven store despite
the fact that the liquor
licence of the store permitted only the sale of table wine.
[3] A
Magistrates’ Court has no jurisdiction to declare the provisions of an Act
of Parliament to be unconstitutional. At each
of the trials the appellant
concerned applied in terms of section 103(3) of the interim Constitution for a
postponement of the trial
to enable the constitutional issue to be referred to
this Court for determination.[4] On
each occasion the application was refused and the trial proceeded. The trials
followed the same pattern. The appellants admitted
the material allegations
made in the charge sheets, indicated that they would challenge the
constitutionality of the provisions of
the Liquor Act on which the charges were
based, and led no evidence. The magistrates, as they were obliged to do in
terms of section
103(2) of the interim Constitution, assumed the provisions of
the Liquor Act to be valid and convicted the
appellants.[5]
[4] The
appellants, who had been represented by the same counsel and attorneys at their
trials, appealed to the Cape of Good Hope
Provincial Division of the Supreme
Court against their convictions. In each case the only ground of appeal was
that the relevant
provisions of the Liquor Act were inconsistent with the
interim Constitution and accordingly invalid. The appeals were set down
for
hearing on the same day and were dealt with as one matter. The appellants did
not ask the Court to refer the constitutional
issues to this Court in terms of
section 102(1) of the interim
Constitution.[6] Instead they
conceded that the magistrates had correctly convicted them, that the only
defence that could be offered was that the
provisions were unconstitutional, and
that the Provincial Division had no jurisdiction to set the convictions aside on
such grounds.
The appeals were accordingly dismissed and the appellants then
noted an appeal in terms of rule
21(1)[7] to this Court.
[5] The
scheme of the Liquor Act is to control the sale of liquor through a licensing
system. It is an offence under the Act to sell
liquor without a licence or a
special exemption,[8] to fail to
comply with a condition of a
licence,[9] and to sell liquor at a
time[10] or a
place[11] at which the sale of
liquor is not permitted by the licence. The Act also contains a general
prohibition against a liquor business
being conducted on the same premises as
any other trade or occupation,[12]
but exceptions are made in respect of businesses conducted in terms of a
grocer’s wine licence[13] or a
sorghum beer licence.[14]
[6] Sections 87 to 90 of the Liquor Act deal with conditions attaching
to grocers’ wine licences. Section 87 provides that:
“The holder of a grocer’s wine licence . . . shall at all times carry on the business of a general dealer (which shall include dealing in groceries and foodstuffs), and may carry on or pursue any other business (excluding a business to which any other licence relates) or trade or occupation, on the licensed premises.”
Section 88(1)
prohibits the sale under a grocer’s wine licence of any liquor other than
table wine. Section 90(1) deals with
the time when the table wine may be sold.
The times are:
“(a) on any day, excluding a closed day and Saturday . . . between 08:00 and 20:00;
(b) on any Saturday, excluding a closed day . . . between 08:00 and 17:00.”
A closed day on which sales are
not permitted under a grocer’s wine licence are Sundays, Good Friday and
Christmas Day.[15]
[7] The
appellants contended that the prohibition imposed by section 90(1)(a) on the
selling of wine “after hours” on
week days and on closed days, and
by section 88(1) on the sale of liquor other than wine, which made the sale of
cider and beer unlawful,
is inconsistent with the right to economic activity
guaranteed by section 26 of the interim Constitution and that the prohibition
against selling wine on Sundays was inconsistent with the right to freedom of
religion, belief and opinion guaranteed by section
14.
Intervening
parties
[8] The Minister of Trade and Industry, the minister
responsible for the administration of the Liquor Act, elected to intervene in
the appeal in terms of section 102(10) of the interim
Constitution[16] and to present
argument to the Court on behalf of the government. Subsequently, the South
African Liquor Store Association was admitted
as an amicus curiae and was given
leave in terms of rule 9(9) to address oral argument to the Court at the hearing
of the appeals
which had been set down for hearing before this Court on the same
day.
The evidence
[9] As a result of the procedure
followed in the Magistrates’ Court and in the appeals to the Cape of Good
Hope Provincial Division
the appeal record contained no evidence relevant to the
constitutionality of the prohibitions challenged by the appellants. After
the
appeals had been noted to this Court an agreement was reached between the
attorneys for the appellants and a representative of
the Attorney General that
the appellants would lodge affidavits from experts dealing with the issues on
appeal, that the Attorney
General would be entitled to lodge affidavits in
answer to such contentions, and that the appellants would be entitled to lodge
affidavits
in reply.
[10] Claiming to act in pursuance of this agreement
the appellants lodged affidavits from three experts in which it was said that
the provisions of the Liquor Act limiting the hours and days of sale had no
discernible impact on alcohol consumption, that there
is no legitimate reason
for distinguishing between the types of liquor which may be sold from particular
premises, and in particular
no legitimate reason for permitting grocers to sell
wine, but not beer and cider. These affidavits referred to statistical
information
which was said to support these contentions and also contained
averments that the legislation which permits grocers to sell wine,
but not beer
and cider or other liquor, resulted from political influence exercised by the
“wine lobby” at the time the
legislation was passed.
[11] The
Attorney General, purporting to act in terms of rule 34 of the Constitutional
Court Rules, lodged affidavits in which it
was said that there is a relationship
between the consumption of alcohol and violent crime, and that if restrictions
on the times
at which and the types of liquor which could be sold by
supermarkets were removed there would be an increase in the consumption of
liquor to the prejudice of the community. The Minister of Trade and Industry
also lodged affidavits from experts disputing the averments
made by the
appellants’ experts. At the hearing of the matter counsel for the
appellants tendered from the bar a number of
extracts from publications which he
said had been relied on by one of the appellants’ experts; there was no
affidavit from
the expert confirming this or explaining why the extracts had not
been dealt with in his affidavit.
[12] In their written arguments counsel
for the Attorney General and counsel for the Minister of Trade and Industry
disputed the admissibility
of the affidavits relied on by the appellants,
contending that they went beyond what is permissible under rule 34. They also
objected
to the admission of the extracts from the publications which had been
tendered from the bar by counsel for the appellants.
[13] In response
to the averments made in the written arguments as to the admissibility of the
affidavits, the appellants lodged a
substantive application, in which it was
contended that the affidavits were admissible in terms of rules 19(1)(a),
(b)(ii) and (c)(i)
of the Constitutional Court Rules, and rule 34, but asking in
the event of it being held that the affidavits were not admissible,
that they be
admitted by this Court under its general power under rule 35 to condone non
compliance with its rules. I deal later
with the provisions of these rules and
their application to the present
case.[17]
[14] The
introduction of new evidence on appeal, even in a criminal case, is ordinarily
permissible only in exceptional
circumstances.[18] Counsel for the
appellants contended that this principle is not applicable to an appeal in which
a constitutional question within
the exclusive jurisdiction of the
Constitutional Court has to be decided. In such circumstances, so he argued, an
accused person
does not have the opportunity to tender evidence relevant to the
constitutional issue prior to the appeal. Any attempt to do so
in the present
case would have been met by an objection that the evidence was not relevant to
any issue within the jurisdiction of
the court dealing with the matter. He
contended further that the Constitutional Court is the only court with the
jurisdiction to
receive such evidence, and that it ought therefore to construe
its rules or regulate its process so as to permit such evidence to
be tendered
for the first time on appeal.
[15] The submission that the appellants
could not have placed the relevant evidence on record before noting their
appeals under rule
21 is not correct. There were at least two opportunities
prior to the appeal to this Court when the evidence could have been placed
on
record. First, the appellants could have called the witnesses on whom they rely
to give evidence at their trials indicating that
the evidence was relevant to
the determination of the constitutional issues that they wished to raise as a
defence to the charges
against
them.[19] If this had been refused
the issue could have been raised as a ground of appeal. The appellants could
also have tendered the evidence
on which they now rely at the time of their
appeals to the Cape of Good Hope Provincial Division. The constitutional issues
were
the only defences that the appellants had to the convictions and sentences
imposed by the magistrates and were decisive for the appeals.
The matters
accordingly fell within the terms of section 102(1) of the interim
Constitution.[20] The appellants
should have acted in terms of that section and asked for the matters to be
referred to this Court for its decision,
indicating that evidence was necessary
for the purposes of resolving the constitutional issues. If the Cape Provincial
Division
considered the referral to be in the interests of justice, as it
presumably would have done, it would have been obliged to refer
the matters. It
would also have been obliged to consider the implications of the
appellants’ failure to place the necessary
evidence on record at the time
of their trials. If it took the view that evidence was admissible on appeal, it
would have been obliged
to receive the evidence and make findings thereon before
referring the matter.[21] If it
took the view that evidence was not admissible on appeal, it would have referred
the issues without receiving the evidence.
[16] The appellants did not
avail themselves of either of these opportunities. The first time that they
evinced any intention of
adducing evidence on the constitutional issues was
after an appeal in terms of rule 21 had been noted to this Court. In their
application
to have the new evidence admitted on appeal the appellants did not
suggest that they could not have tendered the evidence prior to
noting their
appeals. They relied in the first instance on a contention that the evidence
was admissible in terms of rules 19 and
34, and in the alternative, on the
Court’s power in terms of section 173 of the 1996 Constitution to regulate
its own process.
Rule 19
[17] Rule 19 deals with the
procedure to be followed in appeals in which leave to appeal is required. Its
provisions are made applicable
to appeals noted under rule 21(1). They require
the appellant to prepare and lodge the appeal record within a period of four
months.
Rule 19(1) deals with the contents of the record. It provides:
“(a) . . .
(b) The appeal record shall consist of –
(i) those portions of the judgment of the court a quo, and all relevant documentation lodged by the parties in the court a quo pertaining to the issues that are to be determined; and
(ii) only such evidence and exhibits or affidavits and annexures as may be relevant for the purpose of the appeal.
(c) (i) The parties shall endeavour to reach agreement on what should be included in the record and, in the absence of such agreement, the appellant shall apply to the President for directions to be given in regard to the compilation of the record.”
[18] The appellants
contended that in terms of rule 19(1)(c)(i) the parties were entitled to agree
that the trial record should be
supplemented by the introduction of new
evidence, that such an agreement was reached in the present case, and that in
the circumstances
the appellants were entitled to rely on the affidavits from
the experts. Counsel for the Attorney General disputed this; he argued
that the
agreement should be construed as one determining the procedure to be followed in
introducing affidavits admissible under
rule 34, and that in the light of the
material dispute of fact that existed on the affidavits, the requirements of
rule 34 had not
been met. I deal later with rule 34.
[19] I shall assume
in favour of the appellants that their version of the agreement should be
accepted. But even if this is so, the
evidence would not be admissible in terms
of rule 19. Rule 19 deals with the preparation of the appeal record, which
according to
the practice of our courts has always been understood to mean a
record of the proceedings in the court against whose decision the
appeal has
been noted. Rule 19(1)(b) is directed to the exclusion from the record of
evidence that may not be relevant to an appeal
on constitutional issues only.
It prescribes a procedure for circumscribing the record and not a means for
introducing new evidence
on appeal. That is apparent not only from the context,
but also from the reference in rule 19(1)(b)(ii) to “evidence and
exhibits”
which can only be understood as referring to evidence and
exhibits already on record.
[20] The interim Constitution requires that
evidence relevant to the referral of issues to this Court be dealt with through
procedures
to be completed prior to the referral. This is emphasised in
sections 102(1), 102(3), 102(15) and 103(4) of the interim Constitution.
The
same considerations that underlie these requirements apply to appeals and
applications for direct access. The reason is obvious.
All justices of the
Court who are available to do so are required to deal with matters which are
heard by this Court.[22] It cannot
be expected that eleven judges should sit to hear disputed evidence – a
matter made clear by the judgment in Brink v Kitshoff
NO[23] which was reported prior
to the noting of the appeal in the present matter.
[21] Counsel for the
appellants suggested that the problem of resolving conflicts of fact could be
addressed through section 7 of the Constitutional Court Complementary Act 13 of
1995 which empowers this Court to appoint commissions to receive evidence
“necessary for the determination of any issue” in
proceedings before
it. The fact that this Court has the power to appoint a commission to receive
evidence does not mean that litigants
are entitled as of right to introduce new
evidence on appeal. It is not necessary in the present case to express any
opinion on
the facts that have to be established to justify the appointment of a
commission under section 7. No application was made for the appointment of such
a commission and all that need be said is that the section provides no support
for the construction of rule 19 on which the appellants rely. In effect, what
the appellants contend is that the parties can agree to the introduction of
disputed
evidence for the first time on appeal, and require this Court to
resolve the dispute, if necessary by hearing oral evidence, and
that this can be
done against the wishes of the Court and no matter how inconvenient such a
procedure might be. Much clearer language
than that used in rule 19 would be
required to justify a conclusion that so unusual a procedure was contemplated by
the rules of this Court.
Rule 34
[22] Rule 34
provides:
“(1) Any party to any proceedings before the Court, and an amicus curiae properly admitted by the Court in any proceedings shall be entitled, in documents lodged with the registrar in terms of these rules, to canvass factual material which is relevant to the determination of the issues before the Court and which do not specifically appear on the record: Provided that such facts –
(a) are common cause or otherwise incontrovertible; or
(b) are of an official, scientific, technical or statistical nature, capable of easy verification.
(2) All other parties shall be entitled, within the time allowed by these rules for responding to such document, to admit, deny, controvert or elaborate upon such facts to the extent necessary and appropriate for a proper decision by the Court.”
[23] Rule 34(1)(a) requires
the facts relied upon to be “common cause” or
“incontrovertible”. The rule has no application to
disputed facts.
Rule 34(1)(b) requires the facts to be of the character contemplated by the rule
and to be capable of “easy verification”. Factual
material in the
affidavits which falls within these parameters is admissible under rule 34; but
disputed facts which are not capable of easy verification are
not.
Regulation of process
[24] Section 173 of the 1996
Constitution confers on this Court, the Supreme Court of Appeal and the High
Courts an “inherent
power to protect and regulate their own process, and
to develop the common law, taking into account the interests of justice.”
Counsel for the appellants contended that if the expert evidence on which they
rely is not admissible under rule 19 or rule 34, this
Court should exercise its
powers under section 173 of the Constitution to admit it. The appellants do
not, however, have to rely
on section 173 which in any event seems not to be
applicable to this case.[24] This
Court has power under its rules to admit new evidence on
appeal.[25] The question is whether
that power should be exercised in the circumstances of the present case. For
the reasons already given
this Court should not, save in exceptional
circumstances, permit disputes of fact or expert opinion to be raised for the
first time
on appeal. Such circumstances have not been established in the
present case.
[25] The introduction of new factual material on appeal to
this Court is regulated by rule
34.[26] In so far as the evidence
tendered by the appellants is not admissible under rule 34, no good reason
exists to depart from the provisions
of the
rules.[27] It follows that only
those portions of the expert evidence that fall within the scope of rule 34 can
be taken into account for the
purposes of deciding these appeals. I will refer
to the evidence relied upon by the appellants when I deal with each of the
constitutional
issues raised by the appeals.
The interpretation of
section 26
[26] Section 26 of the interim Constitution, on which the
appellants rely for their challenge to the provisions under which they were
convicted, provides:
“26. Economic activity
(1) Every person shall have the right freely to engage in economic activity and to pursue a livelihood anywhere in the national territory.
(2) Subsection (1) shall not preclude measures designed to promote the protection or the improvement of the quality of life, economic growth, human development, social justice, basic conditions of employment, fair labour practices or equal opportunity for all, provided such measures are justifiable in an open and democratic society based on freedom and equality.”
[27] The appellants contend
that section 26(1) should be interpreted expansively to encompass all forms of
economic activity and all
methods of pursuing a livelihood. The only exclusion
that they would allow is in respect of those activities which are
“innately
criminal”. All other economic activities, so they
contend, are protected by section 26(1) unless their curtailment can be
justified under section 26(2).
[28] Relying on this construction of
section 26 the appellants contended that subsection (1) constitutes the right
and subsection
(2) constitutes a special limitations clause which displaces
section 33 as far as the limitation of “free economic activity”
is
concerned.
[29] The construction of section 26 advanced by the
appellants does not give sufficient weight to the wording of the section or to
the structure of chapter 3 of the interim Constitution. The words with which
subsection (2) commences, “[s]ubsection (1) shall
not preclude”,
indicate that the two subsections must be read together to determine the content
of the right. Reading section
26 in this way would also give full effect to the
provisions of section 33 and to the structure of chapter 3 which makes provision
for a general limitations
clause.[28] If the expansive
interpretation of section 26 contended for by the appellants were to be adopted
it would mean that the regulation
of economic activity which cannot be justified
according to the criteria specified in section 26 would be invalid no matter how
reasonable
or even necessary such regulation might be. There seems to me to be
no justification for such a conclusion.
[30] The criteria prescribed by
section 26(2) and section 33 are different. Section 26(2) is directed in the
first instance to the
“design” of the measure. If it is
“designed” to promote the protection or improvement of any of the
matters
referred to in the subsection, and is a measure justifiable in an open
and democratic society based on freedom and equality, it does
not infringe
section 26. Section 33 calls for a proportionality
test[29] which does not form part of
a section 26(2) analysis. If sections 26(1) and (2) are read together as
defining the right effect can
be given to both section 26(2) and section 33.
There is accordingly no reason why section 26 should be construed as excluding
the
operation of section 33.
[31] Section 26 is concerned in the first
instance with “who” may engage in economic activity and pursue a
livelihood,
and “where” this may be done. Section 26(1) lays down
that “[e]very person” may do so “anywhere in
the national
territory.” In the light of our history of job reservation, influx
control and monopolies it is understandable
that there should be such a
provision in the bill of rights.
[32] The meaning of section 26 is,
however, by no means clear. There seem to be two possible approaches to its
interpretation. The
first focuses on the meaning of free participation in
economic activity and in pursuing a livelihood. In a modern democratic society
a right “freely” to engage in economic activity and to earn a
livelihood does not imply a right to do so without any
constraints whatsoever.
As Van Dijkhorst J said in Directory Advertising Cost Cutters v Minister for
Posts, Telecommunications and Broadcasting and
Others:[30]
“Section 26(1) goes no further than to enshrine the right freely to be active in the economic sphere wherever one wants – the economic sphere with all its inherent constraints.”
[33] Certain
occupations call for particular qualifications prescribed by law and one of the
constraints of the economic sphere is
that persons who lack such qualifications
may not engage in such occupations. For instance, nobody is entitled to
practise as a
doctor or as a lawyer unless he or she holds the prescribed
qualifications, and the right to engage “freely” in economic
activity should not be construed as conferring such a right on unqualified
persons; nor should it be construed as entitling persons
to ignore legislation
regulating the manner in which particular activities have to be conducted,
provided always that such regulations
are not arbitrary. Arbitrariness is
inconsistent with “values which underlie an open and democratic society
based on freedom
and equality”, and arbitrary restrictions would not pass
constitutional scrutiny.[31]
[34] On this approach to the interpretation of section 26 the right to
engage in economic activity and to pursue a livelihood anywhere
in the national
territory would entail a right to do so freely with others. Implicit in this is
that the participation should be
in accordance with law. Thus nobody can claim
that section 26 gives him or her the right to deal in stolen property or in
harmful
drugs or to break the law in any other way. Nor can anyone claim that
the right entitles him or her to ignore laws having a rational
basis which deal
with town-planning, zoning, licensing, and other regulation of business, trades
or professions. These are the constraints
of the economic system applicable to
all persons and those who wish to engage in it must do so subject to such
constraints.
[35] If this is the correct approach to the interpretation
of section 26, section 26(2) would then be construed as permitting legislation
which curtails free participation as long as the legislation is designed to
serve a purpose sanctioned by the section. Thus the
right to “be
active” in particular economic activities could be constrained by closed
shop agreements or policies of
affirmative action which are designed to meet the
requirements of section 26(2), or by measures within the purview of section
26(2)
which restrict the market, as for instance is presently the case in
respect of commercial undertakings such as rail and air transport,
telecommunications, and
broadcasting.[32]
[36] On
this approach to the construction of section 26 the objections taken by the
appellants would fail. The appellants would have
to establish that they have
been denied the right to engage “freely” in the selling of liquor.
Liquor is a potentially
harmful substance. It is part of the normal environment
in which the liquor trade is conducted in South Africa, and other countries,
for
selling to be regulated by licences which control not only the right to sell
liquor but also where, when and what liquor may
be sold. For reasons that are
given later in this judgment,[33]
there is a rational basis for such a regime which is not inappropriate to the
regulation and control of the liquor trade in an open
and democratic society, or
so constraining or inhibiting as to justify the conclusion that their right to
engage “freely”
in such trade has been infringed.
[37] The
alternative approach is to read sections 26(1) and (2) together as indicating
that all constraints upon economic activity
and the earning of a livelihood
which fall outside the purview of section 26(2) will be in breach of section 26.
This construction
is less restrictive of “free economic activity”
and for the purposes of this appeal I am prepared to assume in favour
of the
appellants that it is the correct approach.
The section 26
analysis on the basis of the assumption made
[38] The meaning of the
words “designed to promote” in the context of section 26 are by no
means clear. Counsel for the
appellants contended that these words should be
interpreted to mean: “constructed so as to achieve”.
[39] This is the meaning that Professor Mureinik suggested should be
given to similar words used in section 8(3) of the interim
Constitution.[34] Section 8(3)
deals with the issue of affirmative action in the context of the constitutional
guarantee of equality.[35] In the
passage relied upon by counsel for the appellants Professor Mureinik said (at
47):
“The words ‘designed to achieve’ can mean (a) ‘intended to achieve’, in which case they mean much the same as ‘aimed at’; or (b) they can mean ‘constructed so as to achieve’. In this latter sense, the wording refers to measures which are not only intended to achieve something, but the design of which makes it objectively probable that they will in fact achieve that something; which are structured, in other words, to achieve that thing. In this sense ‘designed to’ embodies much of the ambivalence of ‘calculated to’, which, although it can mean ‘intended to’, the courts often interpret as ‘likely to’; indeed, it incorporates both those meanings.” (Footnote omitted)
Professor Mureinik was dealing with the
interpretation of section 8(3). Counsel for the appellants adopted his
reasoning and sought
to apply it to the interpretation of section 26(2).
[40] According to the Oxford English Dictionary “design”
means “[t]o purpose or intend (a thing) to be or do
(something); to mean (a thing) to serve some purpose . .
.”.[36] In the context of
section 26 of the interim Constitution this seems to me to be the meaning that
should be adopted.
[41] This does not mean that there need be no
connection between the “design” and the “end” sought to
be achieved.
The requirement that the measures be justifiable in an open and
democratic society based on freedom and equality means that there
must be a
rational connection between means and ends. Otherwise the measure is arbitrary
and arbitrariness is incompatible with
such a society.
[42] In the
passage relied upon by the appellants Professor Mureinik argued for a more
stringent test of legislative purpose –
that there be an “objective
probability” that the purpose will be achieved. He was not, however,
dealing there with
“economic freedom”. To apply that test to
economic regulation would require courts to sit in judgment on legislative
policies on economic issues. Courts are ill equipped to do this and in a
democratic society it is not their role to do so. In discussing
legislative
purpose Professor Hogg
says:[37]
“While a court must reach a definite conclusion on the adjudicative facts which are relevant to the disposition of litigation, the court need not be so definite in respect of legislative facts in constitutional cases. The most that the court can ask in respect of legislative facts is whether there is a rational basis for the legislative judgment that the facts exist.
The rational-basis test involves restraint on the part of the court in finding legislative facts. Restraint is often compelled by the nature of the issue: for example, an issue of economics which is disputed by professional economists can hardly be definitively resolved by a court staffed by lawyers. The most that can realistically be expected of a court is a finding that there is, or is not, a rational basis for a particular position on the disputed issue.
The more important reason for restraint, however, is related to the respective roles of court and legislature. A legislature acts not merely on the basis of findings of fact, but upon its judgment as to the public perceptions of a situation and its judgments as to the appropriate policy to meet the situation. These judgments are political, and they often do not coincide with the views of social scientists or other experts. It is not for the court to disturb political judgments, much less to substitute the opinions of experts. In a democracy it would be a serious distortion of the political process if appointed officials (the judges) could veto the policies of elected officials.”
[43] This accords with the approach of the
United States Supreme Court to rational basis review. It has consistently
held:
“This restriction upon the judicial function, in passing on the constitutionality of statutes, is not artificial or irrational. A state legislature, in the enactment of laws, has the widest possible latitude within the limits of the Constitution. In the nature of the case it cannot record a complete catalogue of the considerations which move its members to enact laws. In the absence of such a record courts cannot assume that its action is capricious, or that, with its informed acquaintance with local conditions to which the legislation is to be applied, it was not aware of facts which afford reasonable basis for its action. Only by faithful adherence to this guiding principle of judicial review of legislation is it possible to preserve to the legislative branch its rightful independence and its ability to function.”[38]
[44] Section
26 should not be construed as empowering a court to set aside legislation
expressing social or economic policy as infringing
“economic
freedom” simply because it may consider the legislation to be ineffective
or is of the opinion that there are
other and better ways of dealing with the
problems. If section 26(1) is given the broad meaning for which the appellants
contend,
of encompassing all forms of economic activity and all methods of
pursuing a livelihood, then, if regard is had to the role of the
courts in a
democratic society, section 26(2) should also be given a broad meaning. To
maintain the proper balance between the roles
of the legislature and the courts
section 26(2) should be construed as requiring only that there be a rational
connection between
the legislation and the legislative purpose sanctioned by the
section. I deal later with how, if it be disputed, the legislative
purpose is
to be established.[39]
[45] The rational basis test fits the language of the section which,
unlike section 33, sets as the criterion that the measures must
be justifiable
in an open and democratic society based on freedom and equality, but does not
require in addition to this that the
measure be reasonable. The proportionality
analysis which is required to give effect to the criterion of
“reasonableness”
in section 33 forms no part of a section 26
analysis.
[46] In coming to the conclusion that section 26(2) calls for a
rational basis review I have given consideration to the decision in
Public
Servants’ Association of South Africa and Another v Minister of Justice
and Others.[40] This case deals
with the meaning of the words “designed to achieve” in section 8(3)
of the interim Constitution and
takes an approach that is different to the
approach taken by me in this judgment. I specifically refrain from commenting
in any
way on the correctness of that decision or on the interpretation to be
placed on section 8(3). That section raises difficult issues,
the consideration
of which must be deferred until the occasion arises for this Court to do so. It
is not necessary to express any
view as to whether the test for rational review
under section 26 is in any way different to the test for rational review under
section
8.
The burden of proof
[47] Counsel for the
appellants contended that the state has the burden of establishing that the
provisions of the Liquor Act on which
the prosecutions were based were protected
by section 26(2). In support of this contention they relied on the approach of
the Indian
Supreme Court to the interpretation of article 19 of the Indian
Constitution and in particular to the way in which article 19(6)
is applied by
the Indian courts.
[48] Article 19(1) of the Indian Constitution
provides:
“(1) All citizens shall have the right –
(a) to freedom of speech and expression;
(b) to assemble peaceably and without arms;
(c) to form associations or unions;
(d) to move freely throughout the territory of India;
(e) to reside and settle in any part of the territory of India;
(f) . . .
(g) to practice any profession, or to carry on any occupation, trade or business.”
There is no
general limitations clause in the Indian Constitution but in terms of section
19(6):
“Nothing in sub-clause (g) of the said clause shall affect the operation of any existing law in so far as it imposes, or prevent the State from making any law imposing, in the interests of the general public, reasonable restrictions on the exercise of the right conferred by the said sub-clause, and, in particular, nothing in the said sub-clause shall affect the operation of any existing law in so far as it relates to, or prevent the State from making any law relating to, –
(i) the professional or technical qualifications necessary for practising any profession or carrying on any occupation, trade or business, or
(ii) the carrying on by the State, or by a corporation owned or controlled by the State, of any trade, business, industry or service, whether to the exclusion, complete or partial, of citizens or otherwise.”
[49] Article 19(6) has been construed as a
limitations clause by the Indian Courts. The section requires laws which limit
article
19(1) rights to be reasonable, and this element – that is,
reasonableness – has to be established by the litigant who
relies on the
limitation.[41] In this regard the
approach of the Indian Courts bears a similarity to that adopted by South
African courts to the application of
section 33 of the interim
Constitution.[42] It is, however,
an approach which is not necessarily applicable to section 26(2) of the interim
Constitution which is not couched
as a limitations
clause.[43]
[50] Indian
jurisprudence is of little assistance to the appellants. The Supreme Court of
India has held that liquor is a harmful
substance and that laws which regulate
and control the sale and production of liquor do not infringe article 19(1)(g)
of the Indian
Constitution and accordingly do not have to be justified in terms
of article 19(6). The constitutional challenges raised by the
appellants in the
present matter would accordingly be dismissed by an Indian
Court.[44]
[51] In the view
that I take of this matter it is not necessary to decide whether, in order to
prove that their constitutional rights
have been infringed, the appellants have
to establish that the constraints imposed on them by the Liquor Act fall outside
of what
is sanctioned by section 26(2) or whether the Attorney General has to
establish that they fall within the terms of section
26(2).[45] I shall assume in favour
of the appellants that in so far as there is any burden it falls upon the
Attorney General.
[52] The purpose of particular legislative provisions
has ordinarily to be established from their context which would include the
language of the statute and its background. Where the purpose is one sanctioned
by section 26(2) the question whether that purpose
is justifiable in an open and
democratic society based on freedom and equality is essentially a question of
law; so too is the question
whether there is a rational basis for the means used
to achieve the legislative purpose. That is not to say that evidence will not
be relevant to these enquiries; it may well
be.[46] The evidence, however, is
more likely than not to consist of “legislative facts”. Professor
Hogg in the article previously
referred to
says:[47]
“The US literature draws a distinction between ‘adjudicative’ facts and ‘legislative’ facts, terminology originally coined by Professor Kenneth Culp Davis, the author of the major US treatise on administrative law. Adjudicative facts are facts about the immediate parties to the litigation – ‘who did what, where, when, how, and with what motive or intent’; legislative facts are facts of a more general character concerning the social or economic milieu which gave rise to the litigation.”
Legislative facts do not have to be proved
as strictly as adjudicative facts and as Professor Hogg says:
“In constitutional cases in the United States there has been a substantial relaxation of the limits of judicial notice for findings of legislative facts.”
I will return to this issue later in my
judgment.[48] For the moment it is
sufficient to say that the nature of the enquiry that has to be undertaken by a
court for the purpose of deciding
whether or not measures have been designed for
a purpose sanctioned by section 26 and the type of evidence that might be
relevant
to such an enquiry, means that the question of “burden of
proof” is likely to be less important than where adjudicative
facts have
to be established.
[53] The Attorney General contended that legislation
controlling the manner in which the liquor trade is conducted is a measure
“designed”
to promote the protection or the improvement of the
quality of life, economic development and human development and as such is
sanctioned
by section 26.
[54] The excessive consumption of liquor is
universally regarded as a social evil. It is linked to crime, disturbance of
the public
order, impairment of road safety, damage to health, and has other
deleterious social and economic consequences. These are legislative
facts of
which this Court can take judicial
cognisance.[49]
[55] The
Liquor Act describes itself as an Act “[t]o provide for control over the
sale of liquor; and for matters connected
therewith.” The appellants did
not dispute that the excessive consumption of alcohol is harmful and that some
control over
the sale of intoxicating liquor is
needed.[50] This much was common
cause.
[56] The means employed by the Liquor Act to achieve this purpose
is to prescribe a system of licensing under which liquor sales are
controlled.
This is prima facie sanctioned by section 26(2). Measures designed to curtail
some of the harmful effects of trade in
liquor are clearly measures designed to
protect or improve the quality of life. This seems to have been accepted by the
appellants
who did not challenge the constitutionality of the licensing scheme
of the Act, or of section 154(1)(a) which penalises the unlicensed
selling of
liquor. Their challenges were confined to the particular constraints imposed on
them by the licensing system. It is
necessary, therefore, to consider the
particular constraints to which objection was taken in each of the
appeals.
After hours sales – the Lawrence
appeal
[57] Section 90(1) of the Liquor Act fixes the times at which
business may be conducted under a grocer’s wine licence. It does
so as
follows:
“The holder of a grocer’s wine licence may, notwithstanding any law to the contrary –
(a) on any day, excluding a closed day and Saturday, sell or deliver his or her liquor between 08:00 and 20:00;
(b) on any Saturday, excluding a closed day, sell or deliver his or her liquor between 08:00 and 17:00.”
Section 159(a),
which is the section of the Liquor Act which constitutes the offence that the
appellant is alleged to have committed,
provides that the holder of a licence
who
“if it is not otherwise an offence in terms of this Act, refuses or fails to comply with a condition which is attached to the licence . . . shall be guilty of an offence.”
Section 163(1)(a) prescribes the
penalties that may be imposed for a contravention of section 159(a) of the Act.
[58] It is not clear to me why the appellant was charged and convicted
under these sections of the Act. Section 159(c) of the Act
provides that any
holder of a licence who
“keeps the licensed premises open for the sale, supply or consumption of liquor or sells or supplies any liquor at a time when the sale of liquor is not permitted by the licence . . . shall be guilty of an offence.”
and the penalties for a contravention of
section 159(c) are fixed by section 163(1)(b) of the Act.
[59] Since it
is an offence under section 159(c) to sell liquor at a time not permitted by the
licence, section 159(a) would seem
to have no application to the case against
the appellant. The same applies to the charge of selling liquor on a closed
day, on which
the appellant Magdalena Petronella Solberg was
convicted.
[60] That, however, is not an issue which could be raised
before this Court, and for the purposes of this appeal it has to be assumed
that
the appellants were correctly convicted under section 159(a). As the case is a
test case in which the appellants seek to challenge
the constitutionality of the
prohibition against selling wine after hours and on a “closed day”
nothing turns on the
fact that the conviction was entered under section 159(a)
and not 159(c).
[61] The appellant’s objection is that the
restrictions imposed by the Liquor Act on the hours during which the holder of a
grocer’s wine licence may sell table wine during week days interferes with
the freedom of such licence holders to trade lawfully
and with the freedom of
consumers to purchase wine at times most convenient to them.
[62] The
appellant has to establish that the particular constraints to which she objects
infringe her right under section 26.
[63] Freedom to engage in economic
activity in an open and democratic society does not imply a totally
unconstrained freedom. Economic
activity is subject to regulation and a shop
keeper cannot claim to have “an unconstrained right to transact business
whenever
one wishes”.[51]
[64] The out of hours sale for which the appellant was convicted took
place on Monday 22 January 1996. In terms of section 90(1)(a)
of the Liquor Act
the appellant was permitted on that day to effect sales from 8 in the morning
until 8 at night. It is a requirement
which applies not only to sales under
grocers’ wine licences, but also to sales under liquor store
licences.[52] These hours of
trading allow more than sufficient time for the appellant or any “
licensed grocer” to engage “freely”
in the business of selling
wine.
[65] The scheme of the legislation is to effect controls through
licences. The licences control who may sell liquor, what liquor
may be sold,
and when and where sales may take place. It is not necessary to deal with the
different types of licences that may be
given or the conditions attaching to
them. Restriction on the hours of selling apply to all licences though
different selling times
are fixed for different types of licences. The
distinctions drawn between the different types of licences are rationally
related
to the differences in the nature of the businesses and no point was made
of this in argument. The basis of the appellant’s
argument was that
restrictions on the hours of sale do not reduce alcohol related problems, and
that an increase in the hours of
sale would not lead to an increase in alcohol
consumption or alcohol related problems. The restrictions on hours of selling
were
therefore irrational.
[66] The appellant’s argument presumes
that a restriction on the consumption of liquor is the only legitimate basis for
restricting
trading hours. This is not necessarily the case, and the Attorney
General in fact contended that the restriction on trading hours
was also
conducive to economic growth and to human development. The regulation of the
hours of trade allows small traders to close
their shops at the end of a long
day without fearing that they will lose trade to larger undertakings that are
able to employ persons
to work at night; it also frees employees from the
pressure of being required to work overtime or at night. These considerations
are relevant to economic growth, human development and fair labour
practices.[53] The case was,
however, argued on the basis that the control of the supply of liquor was the
main purpose of the legislation and
it is on this basis that I will deal with
the matter.
[67] The appellants sought support for their contentions on
this issue from studies undertaken in other countries which are referred
to in
the affidavit of one of the expert witnesses. The correctness of the
proposition that an increase in selling hours does not
lead to an increase in
consumption or an increase in alcohol related problems is disputed in the
affidavit of the expert, Marcelle
Christian, on whom the Minister of Trade and
Industry relies. In her affidavit she says:
“To this day accumulated research has continued to show that:
– Alcohol-related problems are highly correlated with per capita consumption. This appears to hold over time and in different counties [sic].
– Decreases in per capita consumption produce reductions in alcohol-related problems regardless of whether this was from control measures or not.”
And she goes on to say that:
“a large body of recent research studies (30+) has found that relaxation of controls over availability such as expansion of the type and number of outlets; extended days and hours of operation and lower age restrictions, tends to be positively related to levels of alcohol consumption and indices of alcohol-related problems, not only among moderate drinkers, but also amongst so called heavy drinkers.” (Emphasis omitted)
[68] Counsel
for the appellants sought to persuade us that the views of the appellants’
experts should be accepted rather than
those of the Minister’s expert.
The conflict is not capable of being resolved in this way. The expert evidence
was not placed
before the Court in a proper form and the attempt to cure the
defect by tendering unverified extracts from publications on which
the expert is
said to have relied is unacceptable. The proposition relied upon by the
appellants is, moreover, not “common
cause or otherwise
incontrovertible” nor does it depend on “official, scientific,
technical or statistical” material
that is capable “of easy
verification”. In any event the conflict is not decisive of the case.
The question to be decided
is not whether the policy underlying the Liquor Act
is an effective policy; it is whether there is a rational basis for such policy
related to the purpose of the legislation.
[69] What is clear from the
affidavit of Mr Makan – one of the appellants’ own experts –
is that the control of
the availability of alcohol is a recognised means of
combatting the adverse effects of alcohol consumption. Mr Makan acknowledges
this and says that:
“One of the strongest advocates of the Control of Availability theory is the World Health Organisation (‘WHO’). In 1993 the WHO suggested controls on the availability of alcohol . . . as one of [the] cornerstone[s] of its European Alcohol Action Plan.”
Mr Makan disputes
the efficacy of the control of availability theory and says that few governments
rely on it. The means to be adopted
to control the liquor trade is, however, a
matter for the government and not the courts to decide.
[70] I am
satisfied that even if the burden of proof is on the Attorney General to
establish the rational basis, and not on the appellants
to negative it, it has
been established that there is a rational basis for measures restricting the
hours of sale as part of a legislative
scheme designed to curtail the
consumption of liquor. In the circumstances the restrictions do not in my view
constitute a breach
of section 26 of the interim Constitution.
Beer and cider – the Negal appeal
[71] The
provisions of sections 87 to 90 of the Liquor Act dealing with grocers’
wine licences were introduced in 1962 after
the report of the Malan Commission
which had been appointed to consider possible changes to the Liquor Act. The
Malan Commission
recommended that grocers be licensed to sell beer and wine, and
the appellant contended that the only reason for the failure to implement
this
recommendation was the influence of the “wine lobby”. The appellant
contended further that there is no reason to
distinguish between wine, beer and
cider and that it is irrational to permit grocers to sell wine but not beer and
cider.
[72] It is not clear to me why it would be irrational for the
legislature to facilitate the sale of wine as part of a policy directed
to
encouraging the growth and development of the South African wine industry
– a purpose prima facie sanctioned by section
26(2). It is, however, not
necessary to consider this or the Attorney General’s argument that there
is a rational basis for
the prohibition against the sale by grocers of liquor
other than wine that is related to the legislative policy of curtailing the
consumption of liquor.
[73] The prohibition against the sale of beer and
cider in a grocery store does not arise from sections 87 to 90 of the Liquor
Act.
It arises firstly from the general prohibition against the selling of
liquor without a licence, and secondly from section 40(1)
of the Liquor Act
which provides:
“Subject to sections 87 and 99 and without derogating from section 41,[[54]] the holder of a licence . . . shall not conduct his or her business under the licence on premises on which any other business (including a business to which any other licence relates) or any trade or occupation is carried on or pursued.”[55]
[74] The
appellant does not challenge the constitutionality of the licensing system
imposed by the Act or the provisions of section
40 which restrict the goods that
may be sold on licensed premises. For the purposes of this appeal, therefore,
the constitutionality
of these provisions must be assumed.
[75] Section
87 is one of the two provisions specifically exempted from the provisions of
section 40. It provides:
“The holder of a grocer’s wine licence . . . shall at all times carry on the business of a general dealer (which shall include dealing in groceries and foodstuffs), and may carry on or pursue any other business (excluding a business to which any other [liquor] licence relates) or trade or occupation, on the licensed premises.”
The exception
constitutes an extension and not a curtailment of the right to participate in
the liquor trade. It allows grocers the
special concession of being able to
sell wine without being subject to the restrictions of section 40. Having
taken advantage of
that extension the appellant was bound by the terms on which
it was granted.
[76] In his notice of appeal the appellant confined the
constitutional challenge to the provisions of section 88, 159(a) and 163 of
the
Liquor Act. Section 88(1) of the Act provides that :
“The holder of a grocer’s wine licence shall not sell liquor other than table wine.”
Section 88(2) defines “table
wine”. Section 159(a) makes it an offence to refuse or fail to comply
with a condition attached
to a licence and section 163 prescribes the penalties
that can be imposed for a breach of section 159(a).
[77] At the hearing
of the appeal counsel for the appellant did not ask for section 88 to be struck
down. Striking down section 88
would not make it legal for wine and cider to be
sold by grocers; that would still be prohibited by section 154(a) of the Act.
Indeed,
the effect of striking down section 88 might well be to invalidate the
provisions of the Act dealing with grocers’ wine licences,
for without
section 88 there would be no provision dealing with what might be sold under
such licences. If this were to be the result
it would put an end to wine
selling in Seven Eleven stores and make it unlawful for any liquor to be sold
there.
[78] In an attempt to avoid these difficulties counsel for the
appellant asked the Court to order that “to the extent that”
a
grocer’s wine licence prohibits the sale of beer and cider it is
inconsistent with the Constitution and invalid. This, however,
would not solve
the appellant’s problem. The prohibition against the sale of liquor is
contained in section 154(a) which prohibits
the sale of liquor otherwise than
under a licence or an exemption. To be able to sell beer and cider the Seven
Eleven stores must
procure a licence authorising them to do so. And the only
licence in the Liquor Act as presently framed that permits this to be
done,
other than a grocer’s wine licence, is a liquor store licence. But that
precludes the holder of the licence from conducting
a grocery
business.
[79] The fallacy in the appellant’s argument is that it
treats section 88 as the obstacle to grocers selling beer and cider
whereas in
substance the section deals with the scope of the exception to the prohibition
against selling any liquor from a grocery
store. If the appellant wishes to
challenge the constitutionality of prohibiting grocers from selling beer, cider
or any other liquor
the challenge should be directed against section 40 and not
against the exception to the prohibition made by sections 87 and
88.
[80] Instead of doing this, the appellant has approached the Court
for an order that the scope of the exception made by sections 87
and 88 be
enlarged. In effect what the appellant has asked this Court to do is amend the
Liquor Act so as to make provision for
a “grocer’s wine, beer and
cider licence”, as an exception to the prohibition imposed by section 40
of the Act.
A court can strike down legislation that is unconstitutional and
can sever or read down provisions of legislation that are inconsistent
with the
Constitution because they are overbroad. It may have to fashion orders to give
effect to the rights protected by the
Constitution,[56] but what it cannot
do is legislate.
[81] The exception established by section 87 and the
related provisions dealing with grocers’ wine licences do not constitute
an infringement of grocers’ rights to engage “freely” in the
liquor trade. On the contrary they constitute an
enlargement of their rights
under the Liquor Act. If the appellant wishes to challenge the Liquor Act as
such or the licensing system
which restricts the types of business which can be
conducted in association with the sale of liquor, the challenge should be
directed
against those provisions, and not against the exempting provisions of
sections 87 to 90. I express no opinion as to whether a challenge
to section 40
would have any substance; that was not an issue in the present appeals and does
not call for any comment in this judgment.
Sunday trading – the
Solberg appeal
[82] The appellant was convicted of contravening
section 159(a) read with sections 2, 90(1)(a) and 163(1)(a) of the Liquor Act.
Section
2 defines closed day as meaning Sunday, Good Friday and Christmas
Day.
[83] The appellant contends that the prohibition infringes her right
under section 14 of the interim Constitution to freedom of religion
as well as
her right under section 26 to free economic activity.
[84] It will be
convenient to deal first with the arguments addressed to the issue of religious
freedom. The terms of section 14
are as follows:
“14. Religion, belief and opinion
(1) Every person shall have the right to freedom of conscience, religion, thought, belief and opinion, which shall include academic freedom in institutions of higher learning.
(2) Without derogating from the generality of subsection (1), religious observances may be conducted at state or state-aided institutions under rules established by an appropriate authority for that purpose, provided that such religious observances are conducted on an equitable basis and attendance at them is free and voluntary.
(3) Nothing in this Chapter shall preclude legislation recognising –
(a) a system of personal and family law adhered to by persons professing a particular religion; and
(b) the validity of marriages concluded under a system of religious law subject to specified procedures.”
[85] The
appellant contended that the purpose of prohibiting wine selling by grocers on
“closed day[s]” was “to
induce submission to a sectarian
Christian conception of the proper observance of the Christian sabbath and
Christian holidays or,
perhaps, to compel the observance of the Christian
sabbath and Christian holidays.” This, so the argument went,
“coerced
individuals to affirm or acquiesce in a specific practice solely
for a sectarian Christian purpose”, and was inconsistent with
the freedom
of religion of those persons who do not hold such beliefs and do not wish to
adhere to them.
[86] In support of this contention it was argued that the
history of the legislation showed that closed days were introduced into
the
Liquor Act for a religious purpose. Sunday, Good Friday and Christmas Day,
which are the only days presently covered by the
definition of “closed
day” in section 2 of the Act, are all of particular significance to the
Christian religion. When
the interim Constitution came into force on 27 April
1994 the definition in section 2 included another day of significance to the
Christian religion, Ascension Day, as well as the Day of the Covenant, which was
a day of religious significance to a section of
the community. The reference to
these two days was deleted from the definition in
1995.[57] Counsel for the appellant
argued that the selection of these particular days as closed days showed that
the legislation had a religious
purpose, and that this was sufficient in itself
to constitute an infringement of section 14.
[87] In R v Big M Drug
Mart Ltd,[58] a decision
of the Supreme Court of Canada on which the appellant relied in support of this
argument, Dickson CJC
said:[59]
“If the acknowledged purpose of the Lord’s Day Act, namely, the compulsion of sabbatical observance, offends freedom of religion, it is then unnecessary to consider the actual impact of Sunday closing upon religious freedom. Even if such effects were found inoffensive, as the Attorney-General of Alberta urges, this could not save legislation whose purpose has been found to violate the Charter’s guarantees. In any event, I would find it difficult to conceive of legislation with an unconstitutional purpose, where the effects would not also be unconstitutional.”
[88] The Big M Drug Mart
case concerned the provisions of the Canadian Lord’s Day Act.
Its name proclaimed its purpose as did its provisions. It appears
from the
judgment in that case that the Act prohibited any work or commercial activity on
the “Lord’s Day” –
Sunday – as well as any games
or performances where an admission fee was charged, any transportation for
pleasure where a fee
was charged, any advertisement of anything prohibited by
the Act, the shooting of firearms and the sale or distribution of foreign
newspapers. Certain exemptions were made in respect of “work of necessity
or mercy” and the railways were allowed to
operate. There was also a
provision that persons could be exempted from the provisions of some of the
prohibited activities by “provincial
legislation or municipal
charter”. The Canadian courts had previously held that the object of the
Act was to compel the observance
of the Christian sabbath. This led Dickson CJC
to say:[60]
“A finding that the Lord’s Day Act has a secular purpose is, on the authorities, simply not possible. Its religious purpose, in compelling sabbatical observance, has been long-established and consistently maintained by the courts of this country.”
[89] I would have no
difficulty in holding that a law which compels sabbatical observance of
the Christian sabbath offends against the religious freedom of those who do not
hold such beliefs:
“If I am a Jew or a Sabbatarian or a Muslim, the practice of my religion at least implies my right to work on a Sunday if I wish. . . . any law purely religious in purpose, which denies me that right, must surely infringe my religious freedom.”[61]
This does not mean that the selection of a Sunday for purposes
which are not purely religious and which do not constrain the practice
of other
religions would be unlawful simply because Sunday is the Christian
sabbath.
[90] The Canadian Lord’s Day Act had a purely religious
purpose and was designed to compel adherence to the Christian sabbath.
The
provisions of the Liquor Act relating to grocers’ wine licences are,
however, materially different in their scope and
effect from the Lord’s
Day Act and I have difficulty in seeing how they can be said to compel
sabbatical observance or to promote
any particular religion. The Liquor Act
permits the selling of liquor on closed days under certain licences but
prohibits selling
under other licences. Thus liquor may be sold under
“on-consumption licences” on Sundays to lodgers and their guests
at
licensed hotels,[62] to persons
eating at licensed restaurants,[63]
to persons eating at licensed wine
houses,[64] and to club members and
their guests at licensed clubs.[65]
The purpose of the closed day provisions seems to be to curtail the selling of
liquor to the general public on such days. Thus
hotel liquor licences do not
permit liquor to be sold on closed days to persons other than lodgers and their
guests, unless such
persons take meals at the
hotel,[66] and restaurant licences
and wine house licences do not permit the sale of liquor on closed days to
persons who do not take meals
at the licensed premises, though this is
permissible on other days.[67]
Consistently with this policy liquor may not be sold on closed days under a
theatre licence,[68] a sportsground
licence,[69] or under
off-consumption licences such as liquor store
licences,[70] wine farmers’
licences,[71] sorghum beer
licences[72] and grocers’ wine
licences. Closed day sales may also not be made under licences which authorise
sales to liquor traders such
as wholesale liquor
licences,[73] and brewers’
licences,[74] or without the
permission of the chairperson of the liquor board, under a producer’s
licence.[75] Special
off-consumption licences can, however, be granted by the liquor board if
“exceptional circumstances warrant the granting
of the
licence”,[76] and these
licences are apparently not subject to any conditions as to the times of doing
business other than those imposed in terms
of section 32(2) of the Act. This
section does not require that sales on closed days be prohibited and it was not
disputed that
special licences have been granted authorising sales on such
days.
[91] In the present case we are concerned with the narrow question
whether section 90 of the Liquor Act, to the extent that it prohibits
the
selling of wine under a grocer’s wine licence on Sundays, infringes
religious freedom by doing so. We are not required
to consider whether other
provisions of the Act which prohibit Sunday selling under different licences
infringe the Constitution,
nor are we required to consider the prohibition
against sales of wine by grocers on Christmas Day or Good
Friday.[77] I will confine myself
to this narrow question.
[92] In the Big M Drug Mart case Dickson
CJC said:
“The essence of the concept of freedom of religion is the right to entertain such religious beliefs as a person chooses, the right to declare religious beliefs openly and without fear of hindrance or reprisal, and the right to manifest religious belief by worship and practice or by teaching and dissemination.”[78]
I
cannot offer a better definition than this of the main attributes of freedom of
religion. But as Dickson CJC went on to say freedom
of religion means more than
this. In particular he stressed that freedom implies an absence of coercion or
constraint and that freedom
of religion may be impaired by measures that force
people to act or refrain from acting in a manner contrary to their religious
beliefs.
This is what the Lord’s Day Act did; it compelled believers and
non-believers to observe the Christian sabbath.
[93] I am not unmindful of
the fact that constraints on the exercise of freedom of religion can be imposed
in subtle ways and that
the choice of Christian holy days for particular
legislative purposes may be perceived to elevate Christian beliefs above others;
and that as a result adherents of other religions may be made to feel that the
state accords less value to their beliefs than it
does to
Christianity.
[94] Section 90 does not, however, prohibit grocery stores
from doing business on Sundays and in fact the Seven Eleven stores are
kept open
for business on such days; nor does it force people to act or refrain from
acting in a manner contrary to their religious
beliefs.
[95] In South
Africa, Sundays have acquired a secular as well as a religious character. This
had happened before the interim Constitution
came into force and before the 1995
amendments were made to the Liquor
Act.[79] Patterns established over
the years by legislation have resulted in Sundays being the most common day of
the week on which people
do not work. Weekends consisting of Saturdays and
Sundays are times at which most South Africans take a rest from work. Many take
a whole weekend, some take Saturday afternoons and Sundays and some (but
probably a minority) take only Sundays or Sunday afternoons.
Shops are open in
many parts of the country on Sunday mornings and sports stadia and places of
entertainment are also open on Sundays.
There are, however, only very few who
work on Sunday afternoons.
[96] These rest days are recorded in labour
agreements, in business practices, in contracts of service and in provincial
legislation.
Amongst those who observe Sundays as rest days, are many who do so
because it has become the most convenient day for such purpose,
and not because
of any wish to observe the Christian sabbath. The secular nature of Sundays is
evidenced by the ways in which many
people spend their Sundays, engaging in
sport and recreation rather than in worship.
[97] No evidence was
placed before this Court as to how, if at all, the provisions of section 90 of
the Liquor Act interfere with
the appellant’s freedom of religion or the
freedom of religion of any other person, or serve any other religious purpose.
It is difficult to discern any coercion or constraint imposed by section 90 of
the Liquor Act on the religious beliefs of holders
of grocers’ wine
licences or any other person, or any religious purpose served by such
prohibition. The section does not compel
licencees or any other persons,
directly or indirectly, to observe the Christian sabbath. It does not in any
way constrain their
right to entertain such religious beliefs as they might
choose, or to declare their religious beliefs openly, or to manifest their
religious beliefs. It does not compel them to open or close their businesses on
a Sunday.
[98] There is also no evidence as to whether, if there has
been an interference with freedom of religion, the legislation would or
would
not be justifiable as a reasonable limitation of such right. This is an issue
which has troubled the Canadian courts since
the decision in the Big M Drug
Mart case[80] and may have to be
considered by this Court at some future time. That is not necessary in the
present case; nor is it necessary
to decide whether this Court should follow the
Canadian approach or the less exacting approach of the United States Supreme
Court[81] to legislation requiring
“Sunday closing”. In view of the decision to which I have come it
would be inappropriate to
comment on such matters in the present case and I
refrain from doing so.
[99] In the judgments of Sachs J and O’Regan
J reference is made to decisions of the United States Supreme Court dealing with
the First Amendment to the United States Constitution. The First Amendment
provides:
“Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof . . . .”
It is
clear from the United States decisions that although there is an area in which
the “establishment” clause and the
“free exercise
clause” overlap, the two clauses have different concerns. In developing
our own jurisprudence under section
14 of the interim constitution and section
15 of the 1996 Constitution we should be careful not to blur this
distinction.
[100] The primary purpose of the “establishment
clause” in the US Constitution is to prevent the advancement or inhibition
of religion by the state. The primary purpose of the “free
exercise” clause is to permit adherents of different faiths
to pursue
their religious beliefs without being impeded from doing so by state
coercion.[82]. Our Constitution
deals with issues of religion differently to the US Constitution. It does so
under the equality provisions of
section 8, the freedom of religion, belief and
opinion provisions of section 14, and the education provisions of section 32.
[101] The only provision relied on by the appellant in the present case
is section 14. Section 14 does not include an “establishment
clause”
and in my view we ought not to read into its provisions principles pertaining
to the advancement or inhibition of
religion by the state. To do so would have
far reaching implications beyond the apparent scope and purpose of section 14.
If such
obligations on the part of the state are to be read into section 14 does
this mean that Christmas Day and Easter Friday can no longer
be public holidays,
that “Family Day” is suspect because it falls on Easter Monday, that
the SABC as public broadcaster
cannot broadcast church services (as it does
regularly on Sunday mornings, though it does not regularly broadcast Muslim
services
on Fridays or Jewish services on Saturdays or Hindu services on any
particular day of the week), that its daily religious programmes
must be
cancelled, and that state subsidies to denominational schools are prohibited?
These examples can be multiplied by reference
to the extremely complex United
States law which has developed around the “establishment
clause”.
[102] I should add that I can see nothing in the text of
section 14(1) or in the historical background to a constitution which made
no
provision for an establishment clause, which would require such a principle to
be read into its provisions. The Constitution
deals with unequal treatment and
discrimination under section 8. Unequal treatment of religions may well give
rise to issues under
section 8(2), but that section was not relied upon by the
appellant in the present case. To read “equitable considerations”
relating to state action into section 14(1) would give rise to any number of
problems not only in relation to freedom of religion
but also in relation to
freedom of conscience, thought, belief and opinion, which would go far beyond
the difficulties raised by
the “establishment clause” of the US
Constitution.
[103] Section 14(2) does not in my view provide
justification for giving an extended meaning to section 14(1). Compulsory
attendance
at school prayers would infringe freedom of religion. In the context
of a school community and the pervasive peer pressure that
is often present in
such communities, voluntary school prayer could also amount to the coercion of
pupils to participate in the prayers
of the favoured religion. To guard against
this, and at the same time to permit school prayers, section 14(2) makes clear
that there
should be no such coercion. It is in this context that it requires
the regulation of school prayers to be carried out on an equitable
basis. I
doubt whether this means that a school must make provision for prayers for as
many denominations as there may be within
the pupil body; rather it seems to me
to require education authorities to allow schools to offer the prayers that may
be most appropriate
for a particular school, to have that decision taken in an
equitable manner applicable to all schools, and to oblige them to do so
in a way
which does not give rise to indirect coercion of the
“non-believers”. But whatever section 14(2) may mean,
and we have
heard no argument on this, it cannot in my view be elevated to a constitutional
principle incorporating by implication
a requirement into section 14(1) that the
state abstain from action that might advance or inhibit
religion.
[104] There may be circumstances in which endorsement of a
religion or a religious belief by the state would contravene the “freedom
of religion” provisions of section 14. This would be the case if such
endorsement has the effect of coercing persons to observe
the practices of a
particular religion, or of placing constraints on them in relation to the
observance of their own different
religion.[83] The coercion may be
direct or indirect, but it must be established to give rise to an infringement
of the freedom of religion.
It is for the person who alleges that section 14
has been infringed to show that there has been such coercion or constraint. In
my view this has not been established in the present case.
[105] Whatever connection there may be between the
Christian religion and the restriction against grocers selling wine on Sundays
at a time when their shops are open for other business, it is in my view too
tenuous for the restriction to be characterised as an
infringement of religious
freedom. In the circumstances I hold that the appellant has failed to establish
that section 90 of the
Liquor Act is inconsistent with section 14 of the interim
Constitution.
[106] The alleged infringement of section 26 can be dealt
with briefly. The appeal on this ground is no different in substance from
the
Lawrence appeal. Sunday is the day of the week on which most South Africans do
not work. A restriction on the sale of liquor
on Sundays is, therefore, likely
to be more effective in curtailing the consumption of liquor than a restriction
on the sale of liquor
on any other day of the week. For the reasons given in
the Lawrence appeal I am satisfied that the appellant in the present matter
has
failed to establish that the prohibition of the sale of wine by grocers on
Sundays infringes section 26 of the interim Constitution.
[107] It
follows that the appellants have failed to establish that the legislation under
which they were charged and convicted was
inconsistent with the interim
Constitution.
[108] The following order is made: the appeals in the
matters of Rebecca Lawrence v The State, Rodney Gordon Negal v The State, and
Magdalena Petronella Solberg v The State are dismissed.
Langa DP,
Ackermann J, and Kriegler J concur in the judgment of Chaskalson
P.
O’REGAN J:
[109] I have had the opportunity of reading
the judgments prepared in this matter by Chaskalson P and Sachs J. I agree, for
the reasons
given by Chaskalson P, that section
88(1) and section 90(1) of
the Liquor Act 27 of 1989 (“the Liquor Act”) are not in breach of
section 26 of the Constitution
of the Republic of South Africa, 1993 Act 200 of
1993 (“the interim Constitution”), and therefore I agree that the
appeals of Ms Lawrence and Mr Negal should fail.
I cannot, with respect, agree
with the conclusions of Chaskalson P or Sachs J concerning the challenge arising
from section 14 of
the interim Constitution brought by Ms Solberg (“the
appellant”) for the reasons I give below.
[110] The appellant was
charged with and convicted of selling liquor on a Sunday in breach of the
provisions of the Liquor Act. It
is against that conviction which she now
appeals. Her legal representative argues that the provisions in terms of which
she was
convicted are unconstitutional and therefore invalid and that her
conviction should be set aside. There are two constitutional arguments
raised:
first, that the provisions of section 90(1) read with the definition of closed
day in section 2 of the Liquor Act are in
breach of section 26 of the interim
Constitution. As I agree with the reasoning of Chaskalson P on that score, I
shall say no more
about it. The second constitutional attack raises the
question of the right to freedom of conscience and
religion.
[111] Section 90(1) of the Liquor Act prohibits the selling of
liquor by wine licensees on “closed day[s]”. “Closed
day[s]” are defined in section 2 of the Liquor Act as Sunday, Good Friday
and Christmas Day. The appellant in this case argues
that the purpose of this
prohibition is to “induce submission to a sectarian Christian conception
of the proper observance
of the Christian sabbath and Christian holidays”
and that the prohibition is therefore in breach of section 14 of the interim
Constitution.
[112] This is the first case in which we have had to
consider section 14 which provides:
“(1) Every person shall have the right to freedom of conscience, religion, thought, belief and opinion, which shall include academic freedom in institutions of higher learning.
(2) Without derogating from the generality of subsection (1), religious observances may be conducted at state or state-aided institutions under rules established by an appropriate authority for that purpose, provided that such religious observances are conducted on an equitable basis and attendance at them is free and voluntary.
(3) Nothing in this Chapter shall preclude legislation recognising -
(a) a system of personal and family law adhered to by persons professing a particular religion; and
(b) the validity of marriages concluded under a system of religious law subject to specified procedures.”
[113] There is
no evidence on the record to establish the appellant’s religious beliefs.
There can be no doubt however that
she has a direct interest in the
constitutionality of the provisions under scrutiny. If they are held to be
unconstitutional on
the grounds she has raised, then her conviction may be set
aside. If they are found not to be inconsistent with the interim Constitution
on those grounds, then the conviction will stand. This interest is clearly
sufficient to found her challenge to the provisions.
[114] Chaskalson P
has found that in prohibiting the sale of liquor on Sundays, Good Fridays and
Christmas Day, section 90(1) of the
Liquor Act does not constitute a breach of
section 14. He acknowledges that constraints upon freedom of religion can be
imposed
in subtle ways (at paragraph 93) but finds that in this case there is no
constraint upon people’s “right to entertain
such religious beliefs
as they might choose, or to declare their religious beliefs openly, or to
manifest their religious beliefs.”
Nor, he finds, is anyone compelled to
open or close a shop on a Sunday (at paragraph 97). He concludes that any
constraint imposed
by the provisions is too “tenuous” to be
characterised as an infringement of religious freedom (at para
105).
[115] Sachs J, in his concurring judgment, finds that while there
has been a breach of section 14, that limitation is justified in
terms of
section 33. He concludes that the provision contains a sectarian message which
constitutes a breach of section 14 (at para
163). He concludes however that
that breach is justified.
[116] I shall commence by considering the
purpose and meaning of section 14 in our Constitution. Unlike the Constitution
of the United
States, our Constitution contains no establishment clause
prohibiting the “establishment” of a religion by the state.
Nevertheless, the interim Constitution contains a range of provisions protecting
religious freedom. In section 8, the interim Constitution
prohibits
“unfair discrimination” on grounds of religion. In section 32(c),
every person is given the right
“to establish, where practicable, educational institutions based on a common culture, language or religion, provided that there shall be no discrimination on the ground of race.”
And, of course,
section 14 protects the freedom of religion. It is not possible to read this
array of constitutional protections
without realising that our Constitution
recognises that adherence to religion is an important and valued aspect of the
lives of many
South Africans and that the Constitution seeks to protect, in
several ways, the rights of South Africans to freedom of
religion.
[117] The provisions of section 14 themselves are instructive
as to the manner in which the right should be developed in our law.
Section
14(1) protects the right to freedom of religion and conscience. Section 14(2)
then provides that religious observances
may be conducted at state or
state-aided institutions provided that they are conducted on an equitable basis
and attendance at them
is free and voluntary. And section 14(3) permits
legislation recognising systems of personal and family law shared by members of
a religion.
[118] It is clear from these provisions, and particularly
sections 14(2) and (3), that the strict approach of the United States Supreme
Court to the provisions of the First Amendment of the Constitution of the United
States of America in relation to the separation
between state and religious
bodies has been avoided. That approach was perhaps most memorably stated by
Black J in Everson v Board of Education of the Township of Ewing:
“The ‘establishment of religion’ clause of the First Amendment means at least this: Neither a state nor the Federal Government can set up a church. Neither can pass laws which aid one religion, aid all religions, or prefer one religion over another. Neither can force nor influence a person to go to or to remain away from church against his will or force him to profess a belief or disbelief in any religion. . . . In the words of Jefferson, the clause against establishment of religion by law was intended to erect ‘a wall of separation between church and State’.”[84]
This
approach to the First Amendment has led to a jurisprudence which generally
prohibits any state endorsement or funding of religion.
The US Supreme Court
has, for example, held unconstitutional a New York practice recommending the
reading of a non-denominational
prayer in state
schools;[85] has struck down a
Pennsylvania statute requiring that schools commence the day with a reading
without comment of ten verses of the
Bible;[86] and held unconstitutional
a practice whereby public schools permitted the use of their facilities and
released their students for
religious education during school
hours.[87]
[119] The
provisions of section 14(2) of the interim Constitution make it clear that
religious observances at public institutions
will not give rise to
constitutional complaint if the observances meet three requirements: the
observances must be established under
rules made by an appropriate authority;
they must be equitable; and attendance at them must be free and voluntary. It
seems appropriate
to imply from this provision and from the absence of an
express establishment clause that a strict separation between religious
institutions
and the state is not required by our Constitution.
[120] On
the other hand, it also seems plain from the provisions of section 14(2) that
state endorsement of religious practices is
subject to certain qualifications.
First, it should not be coercive. The requirement of free and voluntary
attendance at religious
ceremonies is an explicit recognition of the deep
personal commitment that participation in religious ceremonies reflects and a
recognition
that the freedom of religion requires that the state may never
require such attendance to be compulsory. It protects the rights
to conscience
both of non-believers and of people whose religious beliefs differ from those
which are being observed. Direct coercion,
of course, is only half the problem.
As Black J stated in Engel v Vitale:
“When the power, prestige and financial support of government is placed behind a particular religious belief, the indirect coercive pressure upon religious minorities to conform to the prevailing officially approved religion is plain.”[88]
[121] The
stipulation of voluntariness is not the only precondition established by section
14(2). The subsection requires that even
where attendance is voluntary, the
observance of such practices must still be equitable. In my view, this
additional requirement
of fairness or equity reflects an important component of
the conception of freedom of religion contained in our Constitution. Our
society possesses a rich and diverse range of religions. Although the state is
permitted to allow religious observances, it is not
permitted to act
inequitably.
[122] In determining what is meant by inequity in this context,
it must be remembered that the question of voluntary participation
is a
consideration separately identified in section 14(2). The requirement of equity
must therefore be something in addition to
the requirement of voluntariness. It
seems to me that, at the least, the requirement of equity demands the state act
even-handedly
in relation to different religions. As Brennan J held in
Larson v Valente:
“This constitutional prohibition of denominational preferences is inextricably connected with the continuing vitality of the Free Exercise Clause . . . Madison’s vision – freedom for all religion being guaranteed by free competition between religions – naturally assumed that every denomination would be equally at liberty to exercise and propagate its beliefs. But such equality would be impossible in an atmosphere of official denominational preference. Free exercise thus can be guaranteed only when legislators – and voters – are required to accord to their own religions the very same treatment given to small, new, or unpopular denominations.”[89]
It
is important to emphasise that Brennan J is concerned here not with the
establishment clause of the US Constitution but with the
free exercise clause
which provides that Congress shall make no law prohibiting the free exercise of
religion. Requiring that the
government act even-handedly does not demand a
commitment to a scrupulous secularism, or a commitment to complete neutrality.
Indeed,
at times giving full protection to freedom of religion will require
specific provisions to protect the adherents of particular religions
as has been
recognised in both Canada and the United States of
America.[90] The requirement of
even-handedness too may produce different results depending upon the context
which is under scrutiny. For example,
in the context of religious observances
at local schools, the requirement of equity may dictate that the religious
observances held
should reflect, if possible, the religious beliefs of that
particular community or group. But for religious observances at national
level,
however, the effect of the requirement is to demand that such observances should
not favour one religion to the exclusion
of others.
[123] The
requirement of equity in the conception of freedom of religion as expressed in
the interim Constitution is a rejection of
our history, in which Christianity
was given favoured status by government in many areas of life regardless of the
wide range of
religions observed in our society. Sachs J in his judgment in
this case has provided a valuable account of the ways in which Christian
principles were endorsed by legislation and its practices often imposed upon all
South Africans regardless of their beliefs (see
paragraphs 148 – 152).
The explicit endorsement of one religion over others would not be permitted in
our new constitutional
order. It would not be permitted, first, because it
would result in the indirect coercion that Black J adverted to in Engel v
Vitale. And secondly because such public endorsement of one religion over
another is in itself a threat to the free exercise of religion,
particularly in
a society in which there is a wide diversity of religions. Accordingly, it is
not sufficient for us to be satisfied
in a particular case that there is no
direct coercion of religious belief. We will also have to be satisfied that
there has been
no inequitable or unfair preference of one religion over
others.
[124] I return now to the facts of this case. Under section 90
of the Liquor Act, stores holding grocers’ wine licences are
not required
to close on Sundays, Good Friday and Christmas Day, but are merely prohibited
from selling wine, the alcoholic beverage
which their grocer’s wine
licence permits them to sell.
[125] In my view, it is not possible to
read the inclusion of Sundays in the definition of “closed day” in
the abstract.
The inclusion of Sundays is accompanied, and ineluctably
coloured, by the inclusion of Good Friday and Christmas Day. Good Friday
and
Christmas Day are, without doubt, important days in the Christian calendar. In
addition, many Christian denominations consider,
as a central tenet of their
religion, that Sundays should be observed as a day of rest and religious
observance. It is true that
both Good Friday and Christmas Day are days which
have been declared as public holidays. However they are only two of twelve
statutorily
recognised public holidays. And they are the two days of the twelve
which have a direct foundation in the practice and observance
of Christianity.
It seems an unavoidable conclusion, that these two days together with Sundays
were selected to comprise the definition
of closed day because of their
religious significance for Christians. If the purpose had been to provide for
days of rest, the days
selected would have been all days recognised as public
holidays. The inevitable effect of choosing these days was to give a
legislative
endorsement to Christianity, but not to other
religions.
[126] It is true that the recognition of these days is, in all
likelihood, a relic from a former era when almost all trading activities
and
public sport and entertainment were prohibited on Sundays and religious holidays
for express religious purposes.[91]
For all that it may be an anachronism, it is important to note that the
definition of “closed day” was amended in 1995
by the deletion of
Ascension Day and the Day of the Vow (16 December), but Christmas Day, Good
Friday and Sundays were retained in
the
definition.[92] Whatever the
historical provenance of the provision, its current purpose and effect are to
give special recognition to the holy
days of one religion and not others. That
contravenes the requirement in section 14 that the legislature should act
even-handedly
in relation to religion and not prefer one to the exclusion of
others.
[127] I cannot accept that the legislature’s purpose in
enacting the definition of closed day is a secular one. Even if it
were that
would not necessarily be the end of the matter. In my view, the question in
each case will not be the question of purpose
alone, but the question of whether
the overall purpose and effect of the provision constitutes a breach of freedom
of religion.
[128] I also cannot agree with Chaskalson P when he
concludes that because the provisions do not constrain individuals’
“right
to entertain such religious beliefs as they might choose, or to
declare their religious beliefs openly, or to manifest their religious
beliefs”, there is no infringement of section 14 (at para 97). In my
view, the requirements of the Constitution require more
of the legislature than
that it refrain from coercion. It requires in addition that the legislature
refrain from favouring one religion
over others. Fairness and even-handedness
in relation to diverse religions is a necessary component of freedom of
religion.
[129] In sum, it is my view that the focus of section 14 is
both purpose and effect. In interpreting section 14, we must recognise
first,
the value accorded to religious beliefs and the diversity of such beliefs in our
society by our Constitution; and secondly,
the fact that religious beliefs are a
matter of personal faith and commitment which should not be the subject of
coercion, whether
direct or indirect, by the state. In this case, the
legislation results in a breach of section 14 of the interim Constitution in
that it results in the favouring of one religion over others. The appellant did
not argue that the provision was in breach of section
8(2), the right not to be
discriminated against unfairly on the grounds of religion. It is not necessary,
in view of my conclusion,
to consider whether section 90 would constitute a
breach of that constitutional provision as well.
[130] The question that
remains for consideration is whether that breach is justified in terms of
section 33 of the Constitution.
It is now well established in our jurisprudence
that to pass that hurdle, we must be persuaded that the legitimate purpose and
effect
of the infringing legislation outweigh the extent of the infringement
caused.[93] In this case, we are
concerned with an infringement of section 14(1) of the interim Constitution.
Where there is an infringement
of that right, the infringement must be shown not
only to be reasonable and justifiable in an open and democratic society based on
freedom and equality, but also necessary in such a society. In S v
Makwanyane, the following was said of the different standards of
justification:
“What is clear is that s 33 introduces different levels of scrutiny for laws which cause an infringement of rights. The requirement of reasonableness and justifiability . . . clearly envisages a less stringent constitutional standard than does the requirement of necessity. In both cases, the enquiry concerns proportionality: to measure the purpose, effects and importance of the infringing legislation against the infringement caused. In addition, it will need to be shown that the ends sought by the legislation cannot be achieved sufficiently and realistically by other means which would be less destructive of entrenched rights. Where the constitutional standard is necessity, the considerations are similar, but the standard is more stringent.”[94]
Unfortunately,
in this case, little evidence was placed before us by government of the precise
purpose and effect of the provisions.
It is not the first time that this Court
has been left with little assistance in this regard. Inevitably, the absence of
such evidence
is an obstacle to the exercise we have to conduct in terms of
section 33. It makes it far less likely that we will conclude that
the
infringement is justified.
[131] I accept that if the purpose of section
90 were to provide a uniform day of rest for all South Africans, that would be
an important
legislative purpose for the purposes of section 33. Indeed, it may
well be that the purpose and effect of the definition of “closed
day” in relation to provisions in the Liquor Act other than section 90 is
to achieve a day of rest. That is because other
provisions require the closure
of liquor outlets on closed days. However, section 90 does not require that
grocery stores close
on “closed day[s]”, it merely prohibits the
sale of alcoholic beverages on such days.
[132] It is not clear to me
precisely what the purpose of the challenged provision is, but I am willing to
accept that at least one
of its purposes is to restrict the availability of
liquor on closed days in order to restrict consumption. Such a purpose or
effect
is sufficient to ensure that there is no breach of section 26 of the
interim Constitution, but it is far less persuasive in relation
to the breach of
section 14. This is so because even if one of its purposes is the restriction
of supply to restrict consumption,
it is hard to conclude that this is the
primary purpose of the definition of closed day in section 90(1). First,
because the Liquor
Act does not prohibit the sale of all liquor on closed days,
only certain types of sale. In addition, it does not prohibit sale
on
non-religious public holidays, such as the Day of Goodwill (26 December), New
Year’s Day or Family Day (the day after Easter
Sunday), when the roads are
particularly full and the restriction of consumption would appear to be
particularly desirable. To the
extent, therefore, that this is a purpose of the
legislation I cannot consider it to weigh heavily for the purposes of
proportionality
in the context of a breach of section 14. Nor am I satisfied
that this purpose of the legislation is effectively achieved. To the
extent
that the Liquor Act permits the consumption of liquor in a variety of
circumstances on closed days, it is not clear at all
how effective it is in
achieving a restriction of consumption by prohibiting sales from grocery stores
and liquor stores. On the
other hand, in identifying as closed days, days of
Christian significance, the legislature displays an endorsement of Christianity
in conflict with the Constitution. It is true that the scope of the
infringement of section 14 is not severe or egregious, but in
my view, the
purpose and the effect of the legislation is not sufficient to meet the test of
justification required by section 33.
[133] In terms of section 98(5) of
the interim Constitution, when this Court finds that a provision in a law is
unconstitutional it
must declare it to be invalid to the extent of its
unconstitutionality. In this case, I have found that the prohibition on trading
upon closed days contained in section 90(1) of the Liquor Act is
unconstitutional. Section 90(1) provides as follows:
“The holder of a grocer’s wine licence may, notwithstanding any law to the contrary –
(a) on any day, excluding a closed day and Saturday, sell or deliver his or her liquor between 08:00 and 20:00;
(b) on any Saturday, excluding a closed day, sell or deliver his or her liquor between 08:00 and 17:00.”
In
my view, the constitutionality of section 90(1) could be cured by the excision
of the words “closed day and” from section
90(1)(a) and the phrase
“excluding a closed day” in section 90(1)(b).
[134] For these
reasons, I cannot concur in the order of Chaskalson P concerning the appeal of
Ms Solberg.
Goldstone J and Madala J concur in the judgment of
O’Regan J.
SACHS J:
[135] The relevant facts of the
case are set out in the judgment of Chaskalson P at paragraphs 1 to 4. My
judgment deals only with
the challenge based on the conviction for selling wine
on a Sunday.
[136] On the face of it, the prohibition of the sale of
liquor by grocery stores on Sundays has nothing to do with freedom of religion.
It applies equally to all sellers and purchasers of liquor, operating
independently of their religious persuasion, and making no
distinction between
believers and non-believers. It in no way interferes with the practice of
religion as internationally
understood.[95] I am unaware
of any form of worship, observance, practice or teaching that actually requires
the sale of liquor on Sunday or that
is directly inhibited by its not being sold
on that day.[96]
The
problems
[137] There are two ways, however, in which the
determination of Sundays as closed days for the sale of liquor by grocery stores
might
involve violations of section 14 of the interim
Constitution.[97] The first relates
to the impact that the choice by the state of the Christian sabbath as a closed
day might have on non-Christian
liquor sellers who, because their religion
obliges them to cease trading on a different sabbath on top of the statutory
limit on
trading on the closed day, are placed at a competitive disadvantage.
In the trenchant words of Stewart J of the US Supreme Court
(dissenting):
“Pennsylvania has passed a law which compels an Orthodox Jew to choose between his religious faith and his economic survival. That is a cruel choice. It is a choice which I think no State can constitutionally demand. For me this is not something that can be swept under the rug and forgotten in the interest of enforced Sunday togetherness. I think the impact of this law upon these appellants grossly violates their constitutional right to the free exercise of their religion.”[98]
[138] The
second way in which section 14 might be involved is through the negative
radiating symbolic effect that state endorsement
of the Christian sabbath might
have. The manner in which this might happen is well brought out in a passage
from a judgment by O’Connor
J of the US Supreme Court:
“The Establishment Clause[[99]] prohibits government from making adherence to a religion relevant in any way to a person’s standing in the political community. Government can run afoul of that prohibition in two principal ways. One is excessive entanglement with religious institutions, which may interfere with the independence of the institutions, give the institutions access to government or governmental powers not fully shared by nonadherents of the religion, and foster the creation of political constituencies defined along religious lines. . . . The second and more direct infringement is government endorsement or disapproval of religion. Endorsement sends a message to nonadherents that they are outsiders, not full members of the political community, and an accompanying message to adherents that they are insiders, favored members of the political community. Disapproval sends the opposite message.”[100]
The
question in the present case is whether the prohibition of the sale of liquor by
grocery stores on Sundays amounts to such an
endorsement, thereby sending out a
message that is inclusionary for some and exclusionary for others in violation
of section 14.
It should be emphasised that the constitutional enquiry in the
present matter in no way relates to the rights of Christians to observe
Sunday
as a day of special religious
significance.[101] There can
indeed be no doubt that such rights are firmly protected by section 14. What is
in issue is the authority of the state
to impose a particular religious view on
the whole of society.
The difficulties
[139] In
responding to the question in the context of the facts of the present case, I
have encountered two major difficulties. The
first relates to the scope that
should be granted to the operation of the maxim that the law does not concern
itself with trifles
(de minimis non curat lex) in the area of belief and
conscience. The second concerns whether or not it is appropriate or even
possible to apply objective criteria
when determining the significance law has
in respect of something as subjective and personal as religious belief. The
problem that
faces a court in a multi-faith country is to decide whose viewpoint
or frame of reference should be adopted when such an evaluation
is made.
[140] To complicate the matter further, the challenge based on section
14 came not from believers whose faith was being threatened,
but from grocers
whose profits were being limited. The applicants were, of course, quite
entitled to raise the issue of the constitutionality,
in terms of section 14, of
a law which placed restrictions on their commercial activities. Yet, the result
was an air of artificiality
in relation to this aspect of the
case,[102] and a lack of evidence,
from the side both of the applicants and of the state, on the question of the
purpose and impact of closed
days. If ever there was a case which required
close contextual rather than purely abstract analysis, it was this one, and if
ever
a cupboard was bare of concrete contextual information it was the one in
the present matter.
The text and context of the interim
Constitution
[141] Our solutions to all these problems and
difficulties will, of course, be found not in the complex and often
contradictory[103] North American
jurisprudence on the subject but in the text and context of our own
Constitution. In Prinsloo v Van der Linde and
Another[104] this Court
cautioned against simplistic transplantation into our jurisprudence of formulae,
modes of classification and legal doctrine
developed in other countries where
the constitutional texts and socio-historical situations were different from
ours.[105] At the same time we
stated that in developing doctrine we had to take account both of our specific
situation and of problems which
we shared with all
humanity.[106] Furthermore,
section 35(1)[107] required us
when interpreting the bill of rights to promote the values of an open and
democratic society based on freedom and equality.
We emphasized that we should
be astute not to lay down sweeping interpretations at this stage but should
allow doctrine to develop
slowly and, hopefully, surely, on a case by case basis
with special emphasis on the actual context in which each problem
arose.[108] Although our
observations in that case were specially directed towards the interpretation of
section 8 equality rights in our country,
they can, in my view, be applied with
profit to the interpretation of section 14 as well. It is with these
considerations in mind
that my analysis proceeds. If I draw on statements by
certain United States Supreme Court justices, I do so not because I treat
their
decisions as precedents to be applied in our courts, but because their dicta
articulate in an elegant and helpful manner problems
which face any modern court
dealing with what has loosely been called church/state relations. Thus, though
drawn from another legal
culture they express values and dilemmas in a way which
I find most helpful in elucidating the meaning of our own constitutional
text.
[142] The principal provision in our Constitution we have to consider is
section 14. Headed “Religion, belief and opinion”,
its first
subsection reads as follows:
“14(1) Every person shall have the right to freedom of conscience, religion, thought, belief and opinion, which shall include academic freedom in institutions of higher learning.”
This is
the central provision as far as our enquiry is concerned, but it by no means
exhausts the text with regard to questions of
religion, belief and opinion. In
the first place, the drafters of the interim Constitution emphasized the
importance of section
14 rights by providing that they could not be derogated
from during a state of emergency (section 34(5)(c)), and furthermore, that
they
should be amongst the relatively small number of rights which could only be
limited (in terms of section
33(1)(b)(aa))[109] on the
condition that such limitation was not only reasonable but also
“necessary”. Secondly, section 8 complements
section 14 by
identifying discrimination on the grounds of religion, conscience and belief as
presumptively constituting unfair discrimination.
Thirdly, section 17
guarantees that everyone shall have the right to freedom of association, which
clearly includes the right of religious
bodies to function freely as part of
civil society.[110]
[143] Fourthly, section 14(2) provides that:
“Without derogating from the generality of subsection (1), religious observances may be conducted at state or state-aided institutions under rules established by an appropriate authority for that purpose, provided that such religious observances are conducted on an equitable basis and attendance at them is free and voluntary.”
This subsection has been
referred to as “a prime example of a provision attesting to the
negotiators’ unwillingness to
erect walls of separation between church and
state”,[111] allowing for
the conduct of religious observances at state or state-aided institutions,
which, subject to certain conditions to be
strictly adhered to, would include
educational institutions, prisons, and state hospitals.
Fifthly, section
14(3) opens the way to the possible recognition of religiously based family law
by providing:
“(3) Nothing in this Chapter shall preclude legislation recognising –
(a) a system of personal and family law adhered to by persons professing a particular religion; and
(b) the validity of marriages concluded under a system of religious law subject to specified procedures.”
[144] Sixthly,
the language provisions also testify to the importance which the interim
Constitution attributes to religion as part
of national life and culture.
Section 3(10)(c) provides that:
“The Pan South African Language Board shall be responsible for promoting respect for and the development of German, Greek, Gujerati, Hindi, Portuguese, Tamil, Telegu, Urdu and other languages used by communities in South Africa, as well as Arabic, Hebrew and Sanskrit and other languages used for religious purposes.” (My emphasis)
Seventhly, section 32(c)
provides that every person shall have the right:
“to establish, where practicable, educational institutions based on a common culture, language or religion, provided that there shall be no discrimination on the ground of race.”
And, eighthly,
persons taking official oaths are offered the choice either of swearing the oath
and adding the words “So help
me God”, or else of making a solemn
affirmation without reference to
God.[112]
[145] There are
other provisions which, although not directly concerned with religion and
belief, have an important bearing on how
section 14 should be interpreted. It
is noteworthy, for example, that section 15(1) provides inter alia that every
person shall
have the right to freedom of expression and freedom of artistic
creativity and scientific research, while section 15(2) requires
that all media
financed by or under the control of the state shall be regulated in a manner
which ensures impartiality and the expression
of a diversity of opinion.
Freedom of opinion and freedom of expression go hand in hand, and this section
testifies to a strong
constitutional concern for openness and
diversity.
[146] The same theme is adverted to in the limitations
clause[113] and the interpretation
clause,[114] both of which
establish the notions of an open and democratic society as a primary
point of reference for evaluating the bill of rights. The concept of an open
society must indeed
be regarded as one of the central features of the bill of
rights and a key element in the interpretation of section 14. Such a society
is
a pluralistic one in which there is no official orthodoxy or faith. In the
ringing words of the US Supreme Court:
“If there is any fixed star in our constitutional constellation, it is that no official, high or petty, can prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other matters of opinion or force citizens to confess by word or act their faith therein.”[115]
[147] Further
evidence of the importance attributed by our Constitution to the respect for
diversity is contained in the
postscript,[116] where the
emphasis on reconciliation so as to overcome the strife and division of the
past, underlines the importance of tolerance
and mutual accommodation as one of
the underpinnings of our new constitutional order. Openness coupled with
diversity presupposes
that persons may on their own, or in community with
others, express the right to be different in belief or behaviour, without
sacrificing
any of the entitlements of the right to be the same in terms of
common citizenship.
[148] To my mind, read in the context of all of the
above provisions and of the Constitution as a whole, section 14 was intended at
least to uphold the following principles and values: South Africa is an open and
democratic society with a non-sectarian state that
guarantees freedom of
worship; is respectful of and accommodatory towards, rather than hostile to or
walled-off from, religion; acknowledges
the multi-faith and multi-belief nature
of the country; does not favour one religious creed or doctrinal truth above
another; accepts
the intensely personal nature of individual conscience and
affirms the intrinsically voluntary and non-coerced character of belief;
respects the rights of non-believers; and does not impose orthodoxies of thought
or require conformity of conduct in terms of any
particular
world-view.[117] The
Constitution, then, is very much about the acknowledgement by the state of
different belief systems and their accommodation
within a non-hierarchical
framework of equality and non-discrimination. It follows that the state does
not take sides on questions
of religion. It does not impose belief, grant
privileges to or impose disadvantages on adherents of any particular belief,
require
conformity in matters simply of belief, involve itself in purely
religious controversies, or marginalise people who have different
beliefs.
State bias in the pre-constitutional
period
[149] In the pre-constitutional era there were a number of
statutory provisions with a religious foundation that in no way purported
to
maintain neutrality in relation to “different confessional
alignments”.[118] According
to Professor J D van der Vyver, writing in 1986, “[i]n cases where the
legislature . . . expressed a particular
religious preference it . . . clearly
sided with
Christianity.”[119] He
points out that the Publications Act 42 of 1974 “seemingly subject[ed] the
entire censorship system to the dictates of
Christian
morality.”[120]
Furthermore, primary and secondary education in public schools for white
children was based on the principle of Christian national
education, while
education in black schools had to have a Christian
character.[121] A further
indication of Christian bias in the law was that the crime of blasphemy
“applied to the slandering of the God confessed
by Christianity
only”. His survey goes on to point out that “[t]he Christian bias
of certain branches of statutory law
[was] also evidenced by a series of Sunday
observance laws covering a wide range of regulative and prescriptive
measures.”[122] In broad
outline, the legislation fell into two main categories, namely, commercial and
labour law, and public entertainment and
recreation. The former included
restraints on retail trade on Sundays and a number of detailed Sabbatarian
prescriptions relating
to bills of exchange, pegging of claims to mineral
rights, and conducting the business of butchers and fishmongers. The latter
cluster
of penal statutes declared it an offence on Sundays to show films or
permit public entertainment at a place where an admission fee
was charged, while
in Natal horse-racing on this day was unlawful even if gratuitous, as was
dancing at a place of amusement or recreation
in the Orange Free
State.[123]
[150] It should
be noted that in almost all of the above cases the restrictions extended not
only to Sundays, but to what Professor
Van der Vyver referred to as all public
holidays “with a religious base”, namely, Good Friday, Ascension
Day, the Day
of the Vow and Christmas
Day.[124] Ascension Day is no
longer a public holiday, and the Day of the Vow is now the Day of
Reconciliation, so that the only holidays
with a religious base that survive are
Good Friday and Christmas
Day.[125]
[151] Not only
did the state require observance of certain aspects of the Christian religion,
it also refused to recognise the validity
of marriages that did not conform to
the Christian prototype.[126] The
identification of Christianity with what a judge called “civilized
peoples”[127] emphasized the
role of the Christian religion as a specific source of values for the
interpretation and development of the law.
The hurt caused by the
non-recognition of Hindu and Muslim marriages by the courts has been well
documented.[128] Comparing the
old situation to the new, Farlam J recently indicated his agreement with the
proposition that:
“. . . it is quite inimical to all the values of the new South Africa for one group to impose its values on another and that the Courts should only brand a contract as offensive to public policy if it is offensive to those values which are shared by the community at large, by all right-thinking people in the community and not only by one section of it. It is clear, in my view, that in the Ismail case the views (or presumed views) of only one group in our plural society were taken into account.”[129]
The
contract to which he referred related to property arrangements pursuant to a
Muslim marriage.[130] In a later
case, Mahomed DP speaking for this Court had this to say on the lack of
recognition accorded to Muslim marriages:
“Unions which have been solemnised in terms of the tenets of the Islamic faith, for example, are not recognised in our law because such a system permits polygamy in marriage. It matters not that the actual union is in fact monogamous. As long as the religion permits polygamy, the union is ‘potentially polygamous’ and for that reason, said to be against public policy. The result must therefore be that the father of a child born pursuant to such a religious union would not have the same rights as the mother in adoption proceedings pursuant to s 18 of the Act. The child would not have the status of ‘legitimacy’ and the consent of the father to the adoption would therefore not be necessary, notwithstanding the fact that such a union, for example under Islamic law, might have required a very public ceremony, special formalities and onerous obligations for both parents in terms of the relevant rules of Islamic law applicable.”[131] (Footnotes omitted)
[152] The marginalisation of communities
of Hindu and Muslim persuasion flowed from and reinforced a tendency for the
norms of “Christian
civilisation” to be regarded as points of
departure, and for Hindu and Muslim norms to be relegated to the space of the
deviant
“Other”. Any echo today of the superior status in public
law once enjoyed by Christianity must therefore be understood
as a reminder of
the subordinate position to which followers of other faiths were formerly
subjected. Indeed, the concern expressed
by O’Connor J about the message
sent by state endorsement of religion to non-adherents to the effect that they
are outsiders
and not full members of the political community, has special
resonance in South Africa. Religious marginalisation in the past coincided
strongly in our country with racial discrimination, social exclusion and
political disempowerment. Similar although not identical
observations may be
made about anti-semitism, which targeted members of the Jewish community for
disadvantageous treatment in the
public as well as the private
sphere.[132] Thus, any
endorsement by the state today of Christianity as a privileged religion not only
disturbs the general principle of impartiality
in relation to matters of belief
and opinion, but also serves to activate memories of painful past discrimination
and disadvantage
based on religious affiliation.
[153] Professor Laurence
H Tribe points out further, correctly in my view, that any actual or perceived
alliance between government
and religion can undermine free political discourse.
“The more political leaders wrap themselves in the mantle of
religion,”
he writes “the more readily those who oppose them may be
accused of opposing God. That, in turn, may polarize citizens and
leaders
around a religious axis, creating the sort of divisiveness that the first
amendment was partly intended to
minimize.”[133] Finally, we
should remember that the movement for freedom of belief has preceded every other
in the history of the struggle for
human rights and fundamental
freedoms,[134] while conversely,
religious persecution, sectarian strife, and ideological totalitarianism have
undermined democracy and respect
for fundamental rights in many parts of the
world. State enforcement of a particular belief or ideology can in an extreme
case do
more than marginalise citizens and block free debate, it can threaten
the whole system of constitutional democracy. The present
case, of course,
comes nowhere near raising these distressing spectres, but it does highlight how
sensitive these matters are, and
how potentially deep the implications of
apparently harmless provisions may be. Painful history in our country and
abroad reminds
us that the values underlying section 14 can never be taken for
granted, and must always be jealously nurtured. At the same time
the wide range
of matters covered also indicates how broad and varied the spectrum of potential
violations is, starting with the
most minor infraction which barely impinges
upon the values protected by the section, and extending to the most egregious
invasion
which threatens the whole constitutional order. The appropriate
location of the challenged law in this spectrum will accordingly
have a
significant influence on the way in which it will to be
evaluated.
Competitive disadvantage because of
Religion
[154] As I have said, although the section 14 issue of
principle is real, the way it came to us was artificial. The objective was
to
abolish a commercial restraint, not to secure a religious freedom. Thus, the
matter before us arises out of a prosecution of
an employee of a grocery chain
store whose actual complaint was that she was compelled by the state not to sell
liquor on a Sunday.
She did not allege that she was obliged by her religion not
to sell liquor on a day other than Sunday as well, and, as a result
of her
belief, subjected by the state to an invidious choice between following her
religion or pursuing her trade. Nevertheless,
it was not a precondition for her
bringing of the case that she establish that her own rights of religion, belief
or opinion were
trespassed upon. It was sufficient for her to complain that her
rights were infringed as a result of her being prosecuted in terms
of a
statutory provision which, objectively speaking, was invalid because it violated
section 14.
[155] As a result, however, of what appears to have been the
tacking on of a complaint of Sabbatarian disadvantage to a more general
charge
of unconstitutional commercial regulation, no evidence was placed before us to
indicate whether in practice there actually
was such competitive disadvantage.
Furthermore, we have no clear factual foundation for deciding whether, if it did
exist, it was
substantial or trivial. General knowledge does not provide much
help. Because the tenets of Islam, as I understand them, prohibit
the use or
distribution of liquor at any time on any day, Muslim shopkeepers could hardly
be expected to complain. Orthodox Jews
might feel that by closing their stores
on Saturday and not selling liquor on Sunday as well, they were at some
commercial disadvantage
because Sunday was chosen as the closed day and not
Saturday. Whether or not Sabbatarian exemptions should be provided for in the
case of complete cessation of trading by grocers on Sundays is not the issue
before us.[135] One could hardly
require the state to do a survey of Sabbatarian practice and then choose as a
closed day the one that caused the
least inconvenience to
believers.[136] It could be
argued that exemptions would involve the state in invidious determinations of
religious persuasion and subject the affected
persons to the embarrassment of
being forced to make special applications which would emphasise rather than
diminish their non-majority
status. Yet in the present case we are not required
to enter this difficult terrain. We are dealing only with one item on the sale
racks that is locked away while the customers push their trolleys through massed
ranks of foodstuffs inviting purchase, so that any
competitive disadvantage
suffered, say, by a Jewish storekeeper, who because of religious observance,
closed his or her shop on a
Saturday, would indeed be trivial.
Compulsory observance
[156] The mere fact that the closed day
coincides with a day that has its origins in Christian practice cannot
automatically mean
that it continues to serve the sectarian purpose of
compelling observance of that day as a Christian day of rest. Even if Sunday
continues to have special religious significance for many South Africans, it has
also become secularised as a common pause day for
believers of all persuasions
and believers of none. Its special position has been recognised in labour
law.[137] Its origins in
Christianity have no more intrinsically sectarian consequences than does the use
of terms AD and BC to establish
dates in our
calendar.[138] Accordingly, I
find it difficult to accept that state-imposed temperance on a common pause day
is in itself enough to implicate
section 14 simply on the grounds that that day
of rest originated from and continues to coincide with the Christian
sabbath.[139]
[157] It is
not always easy to distinguish between observances and practices that are purely
sectarian, those that are completely
secular and those that combine elements of
both. In this respect, I would associate myself with the broad sweep of the
remarks of
Brennan J in the context of the case which arose out of the public
display by a municipality of a nativity scene at
Christmas-time.[140]
“Intuition tells us that some official ‘acknowledgement’ is inevitable in a religious society if government is not to adopt a stilted indifference to the religious life of the people . . . It is equally true, however, that if government is to remain scrupulously neutral in matters of religious conscience, as our Constitution requires, then it must avoid those overly broad acknowledgments of religious practices that may imply governmental favoritism toward one set of religious beliefs.
. . . .
[A]t least three principles – tracing the narrow channels which government acknowledgments must follow to satisfy the Establishment Clause – may be identified. First, although the government may not be compelled to do so by the Free Exercise Clause, it may, consistently with the Establishment Clause, act to accommodate to some extent the opportunities of individuals to practise their religion. . . . [T]hat principle would justify government’s decision to declare December 25th a public holiday.
. . . .
Second . . . while a particular governmental practice may have derived from religious motivations and retain certain religious connotations, it is nonetheless permissible for the government to pursue the practice when it is continued today solely for secular reasons. . . . [T]he mere fact that a governmental practice coincides to some extent with certain religious beliefs does not render it unconstitutional. Thanksgiving Day, in my view, fits easily within this principle, for despite its religious antecedents, the current practice of celebrating Thanksgiving is unquestionably secular and patriotic.
. . . .
Finally, we have noted that government cannot be completely prohibited from recognizing in its public actions the religious beliefs and practices of the American people as an aspect of our national history and culture. . . . While I remain uncertain about these questions, I would suggest that such practices as the designation of ‘In God we Trust’ as our national motto, or the references to God contained in the Pledge of Allegiance to the flag can best be understood . . . as a form of ‘ceremonial deism,’[[141]] protected from Establishment Clause scrutiny chiefly because they have lost through rote repetition any significant religious content.” (Footnotes omitted)
[158] I am not persuaded, therefore, that the
selection of Sunday as a closed day either imposes unacceptable commercial
disadvantage
on non-Christians in a constitutionally meaningful sense, or that
it results in state-imposed observance of the Christian sabbath
in any
significant way.[142]
Symbolic effect
[159] The main problem, as I see it,
lies elsewhere, and arises from other considerations. The crucial aspects are,
firstly, that
all of the closed days, namely, Sundays, Good Friday and Christmas
Day, are what Professor van der Vyver in pre-constitutional times
called
“religiously-based holidays”, and secondly, that the prohibition
relates simply to the sale of liquor. Putting
those two factors together, there
appears to be no getting away from the inference that although part of the
objective might have
been purely secular, the means used, namely the selection
of religiously-based days as closed days, was intended to acknowledge and
comply
with the sentiments of those Christians who regarded these days as days
requiring special observance. The identification
of these days suggests that
the manifest object was not simply to serve as a means of economic regulation or
as a way of achieving
a measure of temperance at selected times. The sectarian
message might not be powerful, but it is inescapable. Had Sundays and
all
public holidays been included, the situation would have been different, and the
choice of days could have been considered neutral;
had only Sundays been
referred to, the signal would have been mixed. The fact is that Sundays have
been coupled with Good Friday
and Christmas Day.
[160] My view then is
that the identification of Sundays, Good Friday and Christmas Day as closed days
for purposes of selling liquor,
does involve an endorsement by the state of the
Christian religion in a manner that is problematic in terms of section 14. The
functional
impact of the law may be marginal, and its symbolic effect muted, yet
the communication it makes cannot be disregarded. Even if
there is clear scope
for the application of the de minimis rule to the question of some ancillary
economic costs[143] resulting from
being true to one’s faith, it should be used with extreme caution when it
comes to deciding such sensitive and
not easily measurable questions as freedom
of conscience, religion and
belief.[144] One of the functions
of the Constitution is precisely to protect the fundamental rights of
non-majoritarian groups, who might well
be tiny in number and hold beliefs
considered bizarre by the ordinary faithful. In constitutional terms, the
quality of a belief
cannot be dependent on the number of its adherents nor on
how widespread or reduced the acceptance of its ideas might
be,[145] nor, in principle, should
it matter how slight the intrusion by the state is. The objective of section 14
is to keep the state away
from favouring or disfavouring any particular
world-view, so that even if politicians as politicians need not be neutral on
these
questions, legislators as legislative drafters must.
[161] The
strength of the O’Connor J’s approach, namely its all-encompassing
character which lifts it out of formulaic
reasoning and combines the
relationship between purpose and effect, also appears to be its weakness. It
indicates the broad question
to be asked, but not the specific criteria to be
used for the answer. More especially, it does little to establish from whose
standpoint
the message by the state should be considered. What comes through as
an innocuous part of daily living to one person who happens
to inhabit a
particular intellectual and spiritual universe, might be communicated as
oppressive and exclusionary to another who
lives in a different realm of
belief.[146] What may be so
trifling in the eyes of members of the majority or dominant section of the
population as to be invisible, may assume
quite large proportions and be
eminently real, hurtful and oppressive to those upon whom it impacts. This will
especially be the
case when what is apparently harmless is experienced by
members of the affected group as symptomatic of a wide and pervasive pattern
of
marginalisation and disadvantage.
[162] In testing whether in the present
case the state endorsed a particular set of beliefs in a manner which violated
section 14,
I shall attempt to apply the sensibilities and perspectives neither
of what has been called the “reasonable
Christian”,[147] nor, for
example, of the reasonable Jew, Muslim, or Hindu, nor of the reasonable atheist,
but of the reasonable South African (of
any faith or of none) who is neither
hyper-sensitive nor overly insensitive to the belief in question, but highly
attuned to the
requirements of the
Constitution.[148] In my opinion,
such a reasonable South African is a person of common sense immersed in the
cultural realities of our country and
aware of the amplitude and nuanced nature
of our Constitution. He or she neither attempts relentlessly to purge public
life of even
the faintest association with religion for fear of otherwise
descending the slippery slope to theocracy, nor, at the other extreme,
regards
the religiously-based practices of the past to be as natural and non-sectarian
as the air one breathes simply because of
their widespread acceptance.
[163] I accordingly endorse the compactly expressed approach of Farlam J
when he holds that:
“. . . it is quite inimical to all the values of the new South Africa for one group to impose its values on another and that the Courts should only brand a contract as offensive to public policy if it is offensive to those values which are shared by the community at large, by all right-thinking people in the community and not only by one section of it.”[149] (My emphasis)
Such right-thinking persons, in my view, would have
little difficulty in accepting that whatever may be their deep and continuing
special significance for Christians, the survival of Sunday, Good Friday and
Christmas Day as secularised public holidays integrated
into the programmes of
rest, travel and, in the case of Christmas Day, festivity, of all South
Africans, no longer represents state
endorsement of religion. At the same time,
however, they would have equally few doubts that the choice of these days as
closed days
for the purposes of the sale of liquor, and not to establish a
common day of rest, does indicate a maintenance of the pre-constitutional
sectarian bias referred to by Professor Van der Vyver. Accordingly, adopting
the approach of the reasonable non-sectarian South
African conscious of the
values of openness and tolerance enshrined in the Constitution, aware of the
importance in this area of
not regarding a majoritarian view as a national one
and sensitive to the need to show special regard for the sensibilities of those
who may feel excluded or offended by the measure, I come to the following
conclusion: the inescapable message sent out by the particular
choice of these
closed days is that despite the enactment of section 14, the state still shows
special solicitude to Christian opinion
or, to put it more accurately, to the
views of certain Christians, and thereby infringes section
14.
Severance and the limitations clause
[164] As I have
stated above, it is the conjunction of Good Friday and Christmas Day with Sunday
that manifests a state endorsement
of Christianity as a religion requiring
special observance and meriting more respect than other religions. Implicit in
this is the
assumption that Christians occupy central positions in the political
kingdom, while non-Christians live on the periphery. If these
two public
holidays were severed from the rest of the definition of closed days, then, in
my view, the identification of Sunday as
a closed day would not implicate
section 14. Its legitimate secular purpose would then be shorn of its
illegitimate sectarian one.
In the present case, however, severance was not
urged upon us, and we have not heard argument about it. Furthermore, the
prosecution
related to selling liquor on a Sunday and not to selling it on
Christmas Day and Good Friday. Counsel brought these two days into
the picture
basically to serve as colourative proof that Sunday was chosen not as a mutual
day of rest but because of its Christian
associations. For the reasons which
follow, however, I do not find it necessary to decide whether severance would be
either appropriate
or competent in the present case.
[165] In my view,
the application of section 33 resolves the matter. I have stated that the de
minimis rule may have little application in deciding whether or not there
has been an infringement of section 14 by virtue of state endorsement
of a
particular religious creed. I nevertheless believe that the degree of
infringement is highly relevant in the balancing process
involved in the second
phase of the enquiry, namely, the test of proportionality required when
considering whether the intrusion
against the right qualifies in terms of
section 33 as a reasonable, justifiable and necessary
one.[150] This Court has on a
number of occasions emphasized that the test established by section 33 relies on
proportionality, a process
of weighing up the individual’s right which the
state wishes to limit against the objective which the state seeks to achieve
by
such limitation. As Langa J put it in S v Williams and Others:
“This evaluation must necessarily take place against the backdrop of the values of South African society as articulated in the Constitution and in other legislation, in the decisions of our Courts and, generally, against our own experiences as a people”.[151]
[166] The
requirement that limitations on section 14 rights must be not only reasonable
and justifiable, but also necessary, clearly
identifies section 14 as one of the
core provisions of the bill of rights requiring special solicitude by this
Court.[152] It reduces the margin
of appreciation which a test of reasonableness on its own would allow the
legislature, and places special
emphasis on the selection of options which are
clearly not unduly burdensome, overbroad or excessive, considering all the
reasonable
alternatives. In S v Makwanyane and
Another[153] Chaskalson
P emphasised that there was no absolute standard which could be laid down for
determining reasonableness and necessity;
principles could be established, but
the application of those principles to particular circumstances could only be
done on a case
by case basis. The importance of looking at the actual context
in which an alleged infringement is to be evaluated was further underlined
in
President of the Republic of South Africa and Another v Hugo where
Goldstone J referred to the need for “. . . a careful and thorough
understanding of the impact of the discriminatory
action upon the particular
people concerned. . . . A classification which was unfair in one context may
not necessarily be unfair
in a different
context.”[154]
[167] The
reason why context is so important in constitutional matters is well explained
by Wilson J in Edmonton Journal v Alberta AG:
“. . . a particular right or freedom may have a different value depending on the context. It may be, for example, that freedom of expression has greater value in a political context than it does in the context of disclosure of the details of a matrimonial dispute. The contextual approach attempts to bring into sharp relief the aspect of the right or freedom which is truly at stake in the case as well as the relevant aspects of any values in competition with it. It seems to be more sensitive to the reality of the dilemma posed by the particular facts and therefore more conducive to finding a fair and just compromise between the two competing values . . . .”[155]
In
deciding what is reasonable and necessary in the present case we should
accordingly look to the actual dilemma triggered by its
particular facts, and
not deal with it in a formulaic way simply because section 14 has been
infringed.
[168] Although the section 14 right is in general a weighty one,
not each and every breach of the right carries the same
weight.[156] A trivial breach of
a specially protected right might be easier to justify in terms of section 33
than a grievous infringement
of an “ordinary” right. The intensity
or severity of the breach must accordingly be a highly relevant factor in any
proportionality exercise; the more grievous the invasion of the right, the more
compelling must be its
justification.[157] Conversely,
the lighter the transgression, the less stringent the requirements of
justification. Thus, I have no doubt that any
state action which interfered
directly with or compelled a particular form of religious observance would
rarely pass the tests of
reasonableness and necessity, if at all, and then only
if the most compelling justificatory circumstances were established. Indeed,
there is a core to the individual conscience so intrinsic to the dignity of the
human personality that it is difficult to imagine
any factors whatsoever that
could justify its being penetrated by the state. At the other extreme, there
are transgressions of section
14 so marginal in themselves, or so slight in
relation to manifestly legitimate objectives with which they are inextricably
interlinked,
that the burden of persuasion on the facts imposed by section 33
would be far easier to discharge.
[169] With these considerations in
mind I turn to the concrete act of balancing that we are required to do in the
present case. I
start with an attempt to characterise the severity of the
invasion of the right. We may assume, even though it has not been proved,
that
there is some but not very significant competitive disadvantage suffered by
persons whose sabbath happens to be on days other
than Sunday, Good Friday and
Christmas Day. Such persons, as well as Christians who feel that their
religious observances are matters
of private confession that have nothing to do
with the state, are obliged by the state not to sell liquor on these days
because of
deference to a particular form of Christian sensibility. Yet, the
activities involved are so limited that I cannot regard any economic
disadvantage flowing from belief as being substantial at
all,[158] and I doubt whether they
even enter the scales of proportionality.
[170] Of greater significance
is the signal given to the public at large that the state regards the Christian
religion as worthy of
special respect above other religions. In the words of
Professor Tribe, government’s gratuitous use of a religious means is
likely to convey a message of exclusion to all those who do not adhere to the
favoured religion; when such people learn that government
has gone out of its
way to adopt the religion’s tools, they may believe that government must
have adopted its tenets as well,
and quite reasonably feel, in O’Connor
J’s words, as if they are not full members of the political
community.[159]
[171] This is where the problem of weighing things of a completely
different order arises. The difficulty which we must overcome
is how to assess
the intrinsically intangible, but very real (even if rather reduced) symbolic
effect of religious favouritism, as
against the very palpable and quite terrible
consequences of alcohol abuse which the state wishes to diminish. I have
already indicated
the factors which led me to the conclusion that the selection
of days chosen by the state amounted to endorsement of religion in
a manner that
breached section 14. I will now consider in its context how grave that breach
is, or to put it another way, how powerful
or weak the exclusionary message is
which the state is sending by such endorsement.
[172] To begin with,
the negative symbolic effect of such state favouring of Christianity must be
seen in its legislative and historical
context. The closed days are a small
part of a statute designed to control the sale of liquor and not, as in the
Big M case, a central aspect of a statute primarily intended to compel
religious observance.[160]
Secondly, the challenged provisions do not impose beliefs or interfere in a
direct way with observance. They relate to a situation
of favouritism coupled
with indifference, rather than one of orthodoxy combined with persecution, and
represent a relatively insignificant
relic of a vanishing era, rather than a
pungent symbol of continuing hegemony. Even the objectionable
pre-constitutional period
referred to in my historical survey was not remotely
as egregious in respect of religion as it was, for example, in relation to race.
The result is that section 14 must be construed in a context of a legacy of
institutionalised religious favouritism that is far less
pronounced and
pervasive than, say, the systematic racism and sexism which must influence the
meaning we must give to the equality
provisions in section
8.[161] Then, just as the
economic effects on non-Christians are at most of a marginal character, since
grocers are not obliged to close
their stores on certain days, but merely
required not to sell liquor on them, so the symbolic effect of compulsory
observance is
correspondingly reduced.
[173] In the fourth place, the
signal was further muted by the fact that prohibition of the sale of liquor on
closed days was far
from complete, since the legislation in question made
provision for sales on a Sunday by persons in possession of hotel, wine house
or
club house licences, or persons specially granted licences to sell liquor on
Sundays.[162] The more modulated
the prohibition, the less manifestly Sabbatarian the message. Fifthly, as has
already been pointed out, the
days in question have become highly secularised.
Shops, cinemas, sportsgrounds and jazz clubs do thriving business on Sundays.
Significant though Good Friday is to a great many practising Christians, the
Easter weekend has become for the South African population
as a whole a time for
enjoying late summer holidays. To the regret of many Christians, Christmas Day
has become a holiday when,
as it has been said, more homage is paid to Mammon
than to God.[163] The result is
that choosing these days as closed days now sends out a far less powerful signal
than it once would have done. Finally,
there is relatively little sectarian
significance to the prohibition of the sale of liquor as
such.[164]
[174] The
overall consequence is a law that, while indeed offending against section 14,
does so in an indirect and marginal way, imposing
relatively little obligatory
observance, in respect of a matter of slight sectarian import, in relation to
days that have become
highly secularised. The message of inclusion coupled with
exclusion is accordingly a notably subdued and insubstantial
one.
[175] Balanced against these relatively minor infractions of section
14 are strong factors which operate to justify the singling out
of Sunday, Good
Friday and Christmas Day as days when the state makes special legislative
attempts to encourage temperance. O’Regan
J correctly points out in her
lucid analysis that no evidence in support of section 33 justification was led.
Yet, there are facts
of common knowledge to which we cannot blind
ourselves.[165] Sunday comes at
the end of the weekend, consisting of two pause days, the first of which, with
Friday night, is a time of relatively
heavy drinking. Good Friday represents
the first day of the Easter weekend which is a period when there is
exceptionally high traffic
on the roads and when drunken driving constitutes a
specially serious menace. Christmas Day is the first of two public holidays
widely dedicated to festivity. In my view, the state’s interest on behalf
of society in encouraging temperance on these particular
days is a powerful and
legitimate one.
[176] Although contested evidence was placed before us to
the effect that regulation of the sale of liquor in general has failed to
reduce
the damage caused by alcohol abuse, I am unaware of anything on record, or any
information of common knowledge, which suggests
that once such regulation is
regarded as legitimate governmental activity, and once the purpose of reducing
alcohol intake on these
particularly high-risk days is treated as an appropriate
and compelling governmental objective, then such objectives could reasonably
have been achieved by less intrusive means. In this respect it is highly
relevant that it is only the purchase of liquor in transportable
form that is
made difficult, not the purchase of liquor as such.
[177] My conclusion,
then, is as follows: on the one hand, the scope and intensity of the invasion of
section 14 rights is relatively
slight. On the other hand, the dangers of
excessive drinking, particularly on weekends, at the beginning of the Easter
weekend and
at Christmas-time, are grave. Pay packets are reduced, domestic
violence is intensified and exceptionally high slaughter on the
roads resulting
from drunken driving becomes a matter of national concern. There are
accordingly strong reasons for adopting suitably
focused measures which are
designed to and hopefully will restrict the consumption of alcohol on these
particular days and not on
others. I accordingly feel that in the particular
circumstances of this case the legislative restrictions in question are both
reasonable
and necessary.
[178] The result is that I agree with
O’Regan J that the provisions relating to closed days involve a breach of
section 14.
Since, however, I am of the opinion that such infringement is
sanctioned by section 33, I concur with Chaskalson P in his conclusion
that the
provisions in question are not unconstitutional.
[179] In doing so, I
must state that although in general I support the spirit of realism and common
sense which I find in his judgment,
I cannot agree with the observation in para
104 that coercion, whether direct or indirect, must be established before
section 14
can be said to have been breached. The state as the state is
animated by the values expressed or implied in the Constitution, and
by those
alone. By endorsing a particular faith as a direct and sectarian source of
values for legislation binding on the whole
nation, it exceeds the competence
granted to it by the Constitution. Even if there is no compulsory requirement
to observe or not
to observe a particular religious practice, the effect is to
divide the nation into insiders who belong, and outsiders who are
tolerated.[166] This is
impermissible in the multi-faith, heterodox society contemplated by our
Constitution.
[180] I agree with Chaskalson P’s judgment in
relation to the other issues raised, and accordingly concur in the order he
proposes.
Mokgoro J concurs in the judgment of Sachs
J.
For the Appellants: P Hodes SC and AM Breitenbach instructed by Bill
Tolken Hendrikse Inc
For the First Respondent: B Morrison SC and J Slabbert instructed by the
Attorney General, Cape Town
For the Second Respondent: JL van der Merwe SC and SK Hassim instructed by
the State Attorney, Pretoria
For the Amicus Curiae (SALSA): L Wessels instructed by Du Plessis, de Heus and van Wyk
[1]The prosecutions took place during 1995 and 1996 at times when the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1993 Act 200 of 1993 (“the interim Constitution”) was still in force.
[2]Section 88(1) of the Liquor Act.
[3]Section 90(1) of the Liquor
Act.
[4]Section 103(3)
provides:
“If in any proceedings before a court referred to in subsection (1), the presiding officer is of the opinion that it is in the interest of justice to do so, he or she may postpone the proceedings to enable the party who has alleged that a relevant law or provision is invalid, to apply to a provincial or local division of the Supreme Court for relief in terms of subsection (4).”
[5]Section 103(2) stipulates:
“If in any proceedings before a court referred to in subsection (1), it is alleged that any law or provision of such law is invalid on the ground of its inconsistency with a provision of this Constitution and the court does not have the competency to enquire into the validity of such a law or provision, the court shall, subject to the other provisions of this section, decide the matter on the assumption that the law or provision is valid.”
[6]That section provides:
“If, in any matter before a provincial or local division of the Supreme Court, there is an issue which may be decisive for the case, and which falls within the exclusive jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court in terms of section 98(2) and (3), the provincial or local division concerned shall, if it considers it to be in the interest of justice to do so, refer such matter to the Constitutional Court for its decision: Provided that, if it is necessary for evidence to be heard for the purposes of deciding such issue, the provincial or local division concerned shall hear such evidence and make a finding thereon, before referring the matter to the Constitutional Court.”
[7]Rule 21(1) of the Constitutional Court Rules states that if:
“(a) an accused has appealed unsuccessfully to a provincial or local division of the Supreme Court against a conviction or sentence imposed on him or her in the magistrate’s court; and
(b) the grounds of appeal include a constitutional issue within the exclusive jurisdiction of the Court; and
(c) the accused wishes to appeal against the conviction or sentence solely on the grounds of such constitutional issue,
the accused shall be entitled to appeal on such grounds to the Court against the conviction or sentence.”
[8]Section 154(1)(a).
[9]Section 159(a).
[10]Section 159(c).
[11]Section 159(e).
[12]Section 40 of the Liquor Act. In terms of section 41(1)(c) a liquor business would include the sale of “mineral waters, other drinks (other than liquor as defined in section 2(1)), tobacco, cigars, cigarettes, matches, [and] cooler bags . . .”. The list of products may be extended by the chairperson of the provincial liquor board.
[13]Section 87. The terms of section 87 are set out in paragraph 6 below.
[14]Section 99. Any business, other than the sale of liquor, may be conducted on premises licensed for the sale of sorghum beer.
[15]Closed day is defined in
section 2 of the Liquor
Act.
[16]Section 102(10)
provides:
“If the validity of a law is in dispute in any matter, and a relevant government is not a party to the proceedings, it shall be entitled to intervene as a party before the court in question, or shall be entitled to submit written argument to the said court.”
The Attorney General prosecutes in the name of the state under a constitutional authority to do so (section 108(1) of the interim Constitution; section 179(2) of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 Act 108 of 1996 (“the 1996 Constitution”)), and represented the state, not the “government” in the prosecution of the appellants and in opposing their appeals.
[17]Paras 17 – 21 and 22 – 23.
[18]S v Louw [1990] ZASCA 43; 1990 (3) SA 116 (A) at 123G–124A.
[19]See Walker v Stadsraad van Pretoria 1997 (3) BCLR 416 (T) at 425I.
[20]See above n 6.
[21]Id.
[22]Section 100(3) of the interim Constitution.
[23][1996] ZACC 9; 1996 (4) SA 197 (CC); 1996 (6) BCLR 752 (CC) at paras 11–13.
[24]Item 17 of schedule 6 to the 1996 Constitution provides that “All proceedings which were pending before a court when the new Constitution took effect, must be disposed of as if the new Constitution had not been enacted, unless the interests of justice require otherwise.” The appellants rely on this provision for their arguments based on section 26 of the interim Constitution which they see as being more favourable to their case than the comparable provision of the 1996 Constitution, section 22.
[25]See rule 33 which incorporates by reference the provisions of section 22 of the Supreme Court Act 59 of 1959.
[26]It makes provision for the admission of “legislative facts” and other material that may be common cause.
[27]Moulded Components and Rotomoulding South Africa (Pty) Ltd v Coucourakis and Another 1979 (2) SA 457 (W) at 462H–463B; Krygkor Pensioenfonds v Smith [1993] ZASCA 47; 1993 (3) SA 459 (A) at 469E–I.
[28]S v Makwanyane and Another [1995] ZACC 3; 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC); 1995 (6) BCLR 665 (CC) at para 100.
[29]Id at para 104.
[30] 1996 (3) SA 800 (T) at 813G.
[31]Section 35(1) requires the provisions of the bill of rights to be interpreted so as to promote such values.
[32]These are merely illustrations of the application of section 26 and should not be construed as a definition of what is permitted. The restrictions could be imposed on a regional basis which would have a bearing on the provision that economic activity can be conducted “anywhere”.
[33]Paragraphs 54 – 56 and 65 – 70.
[34]“A Bridge To Where?
Introducing the Interim Bill of Rights” (1994) 10 SA Journal on Human
Rights 31 at
46–8.
[35]Section 8(3)(a)
provides:
“This section shall not preclude measures designed to achieve the adequate protection and advancement of persons or groups or categories of persons disadvantaged by unfair discrimination, in order to enable their full and equal enjoyment of all rights and freedoms.”
[36]Oxford
English Dictionary vol IV 2 ed (Clarendon Press, Oxford 1989) meaning 10.
Professor Mureinik does not indicate the source of the meaning
“constructed
so as to achieve” which he explains as meaning
“objectively probable that they will in fact achieve”. None of
the
meanings given to “design” in the Oxford Dictionary has this
connotation. The only reference to the design of laws
in the Oxford Dictionary
is a quotation from Burke given in respect of the meaning accepted in this
judgment: “Ask of politicians
the end for which laws were originally
designed; and they will answer, that the laws were designed as a protection for
the poor and
weak.”
[37]“Proof of
Facts in Constitutional Cases” (1976) 26 University of Toronto law
Journal 386 at 396–7.
[38]Carmichael, Attorney General of Alabama v Southern Coal & Coke Co [1937] USSC 108; 301 US 495, 510 (1937). See also FCC v Beach Communications, Inc [1993] USSC 64; 508 US 307, 315 (1993), and Lehnhausen, Director, Department of Local Government Affairs of Illinois v Lake Shore Auto Parts Co [1973] USSC 64; 410 US 356, 364–5 (1973).
[39]Paragraphs 51 –
52.
[40] 1997 (5) BCLR 577
(T).
[41]Laxmi Khandsari v State of UP (1981) AIR SC 873 at paras 12 and 14.
[42]S v Makwanyane above n 28 at paras 103–4.
[43]See paragraphs 26 – 30 above.
[44]Har Shankar and Others v The Deputy Excise and Taxation Commissioner (1975) AIR SC 1121 at para 53; Lakhanlal v The State of Orissa (1977) AIR SC 722 at para 29.
[45]There is another possible construction, namely that the party that relies on the law has to show that it is designed to meet a purpose specified in section 26(2), and if this is done, that the party who contends that a particular provision of the law does not serve that purpose, to establish that there is no rational connection between the purpose and the provision. Compare Basu Constitutional Law of India 6 ed (1991) at 39.
[46]In the United States the courts do not require evidence on this issue. “[A] legislative choice is not subject to courtroom factfinding and may be based on rational speculation unsupported by evidence or empirical data.” (FCC v Beach Communications, Inc above n 38 at 315). See also Cabinet for the Territory of South West Africa v Chikane and Another 1989 (1) SA 349 (A) at 368A–369D and 382H–383F. As the Beach Communications case shows (at 314–5) the United States Supreme Court requires those challenging the constitutionality of legislation under a rational basis review “to negative every conceivable basis which might support it” (quoting from Lehnhausen v Lake Shore Auto Parts Co above n 38 at 364).
[47]University of Toronto Law Journal above n 37 at 395.
[48]Paragraphs 67 – 70.
[49]Compare Cherry v Minister of Safety and Security and Others 1995 (3) SA 323 (SECLD) at 337G–I; 1995 (5) BCLR 570 (SE) at 584D–F.
[50]In fact this was acknowledged by one of their experts – Mr Makan – in the affidavits lodged by the appellants and was “common cause” within the meaning of rule 34(1)(a). It was presumably for this reason that the challenge was to the statutory conditions attaching to grocers’ wine licences and not to the licensing system as such.
[51]Per Dickson CJC in Edwards Books and Art Ltd v The Queen (1986) 28 CRR 1 at 53.
[52]Section 85(1) of the Act.
[53]In the United States the burden of negativing a rational connection between the legislation and a legitimate government purpose is on the person challenging the validity of the legislation. “[T]hose attacking the rationality of the legislative classification have the burden ‘to negative every conceivable basis which might support it,’” FCC v Beach Communications Inc above n 38 at 315. Whilst a section 26 analysis may call for a different approach a rational basis review is one in which the legislature will be allowed considerable lee-way.
[54]Section 41 identifies the products other than liquor that may be sold on various types of licensed premises. It does not deal with products that may be sold on premises in respect of which a grocer’s wine licence has been issued. That is dealt with in section 87.
[55]Section 99 deals with the sale of sorghum beer and is not relevant to this appeal.
[56]Fose v Minister of Safety and Security [1997] ZACC 6; 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC); 1997 (7) BCLR 851 (CC).
[57]Section 2(c) of Act 57 of 1995.
[59]Id at 95.
[60]Id at 93.
[61]Id at 99. My emphasis.
[62]Section 54(1)(a) of the Act.
[63]Section 57 of the Act.
[64]Section 61 of the Act.
[65]Section 65 of the Act.
[66]Section 54(1)(b) of the Act.
[67]Sections 57 and 61 of the Act.
[68]Section 63(1) of the Act.
[69]Section 72(1) of the Act.
[70]Section 85 of the Act.
[71]Section 93 of the Act.
[72]Section 100 of the Act.
[73]Section 77 of the Act.
[74]Section 81 of the Act.
[75]Section 103 of the Act. A producer’s licence authorises the sale of wine and other alcoholic beverages by the “manufacturers” of such liquor.
[76]Section 20(b)(viii) read with section 22(2)(b) of the Act.
[77]If the restriction in its application to Christmas Day or Good Friday should be seen as having a purely religious purpose which infringes the freedom of religion of non-Christians, I can see no reason why the reference to those days cannot be severed from the definition leaving only Sundays as closed days. That issue does not, however, arise in the present case.
[78]Above n 58 at 97.
[79]See above n 57.
[80]See Edwards Books and Art Ltd v The Queen above n 51; R v Rice (1989) 49 CCC (3d) 1; Peel v A & P (1991) 5 CRR (2d) 204.
[81]McGowan v Maryland [1961] USSC 101; 366 US 420 (1961); Braunfeld v Brown [1961] USSC 96; 366 US 599 (1961); Two Guys from Harrison-Allentown Inc v McGinley [1961] USSC 105; 366 US 582 (1961).
[82]Abington School District v Schempp [1963] USSC 162; 374 US 203, 222–3 (1963).
[83]The Lord’s Day Act dealt with in the Big M case above n 58 is an example of such legislation.
[84]Everson v Board of Education of the Township of Ewing 330 US 1, 15–6 (1947).
[85]Engel v Vitale [1962] USSC 116; 370 US 421 (1962). The prayer read as follows: “Almighty God, we acknowledge our dependence upon Thee, and we beg Thy blessings upon us, our parents, our teachers and our Country.”
[86]School District of Abington Township, Pennsylvania v Schempp; Murray v Curlett [1963] USSC 162; 374 US 203 (1963). Provision was made in the legislation for children to be excused from the reading upon parental request.
[87]McCollum v Board of Education [1948] USSC 27; 333 US 203 (1948). Compare, however, the court’s opinion in Zorach v Clauson [1952] USSC 55; 343 US 306 (1952).
[88]Above n 2 at 431.
[89][1982] USSC 112; 456 US 228, 245 (1982).
[90]See, for example, Brennan J’s concurrence in McDaniel v Paty [1978] USSC 61; 435 US 618 (1978) where he held that “government [may] take religion into account . . . to exempt, when possible, from generally applicable governmental regulation individuals whose religious beliefs and practices would otherwise thereby be infringed, or to create without state involvement an atmosphere in which voluntary religious exercise may flourish.” (At 639, footnote omitted.) See also O’Connor J’s concurring opinion in Wallace v Jaffree; Smith v Jaffree 472 US 38, 83 (1985). And the decision of the Canadian Supreme Court in Edwards Books and Art Ltd v The Queen (1986) 28 CRR 1.
[91]See Sachs J’s judgment at para 149–50. See also the judgment of Dickson CJC in R v Big M Drug Mart Ltd (1985) 13 CRR 64 at 70 where he describes the effects of the Lord’s Day Act.
[92]The amendments were effected by section 2(c) of the Liquor Amendment Act 57 of 1995.
[93]S v Makwanyane and Another [1995] ZACC 3; 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC); 1995 (6) BCLR 665 (CC) at para 104.
[94]Id at para 339. See also
para 104.
[95]The International
Covenant on Civil and Political Rights provides in Article 18(1) that:
“Everyone shall have the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion. This right shall include freedom to have or to adopt a religion or belief of his choice, and freedom, either individually or in community with others and in public or private, to manifest his religion or belief in worship, observance, practice and teaching.”
[96]It appears that in the United States during the Prohibition era, the sale of communion wine was not prohibited. See Stone et al Constitutional Law 3 ed (Little, Brown and Company, Boston 1996) at 1608.
[97]All references in this judgment to sections in “the Constitution” refer to sections in the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1993 Act 200 of 1993.
[98]Braunfeld v Brown [1961] USSC 96; 366
US 599, 616 (1961).
[99]The First
Amendment to the US Constitution reads, in pertinent part:
“Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof . . . .”
[100]Lynch,
Mayor of Pawtucket v Donnelly [1984] USSC 47; 465 US 668, 687–8 (1984).
[101]In this respect I would
like to endorse the views on “Sundays” of Dickson CJC in R v Big
M Drug Mart Ltd (1985) 13 CRR 64 at 108:
“I would like to stress that nothing in these reasons should be read as suggesting any opposition to Sunday being spent as a religious day; quite the contrary. It is recognised that for a great number of Canadians, Sunday is the day when their souls rest in God, when the spiritual takes priority over the material, a day which, to them, gives security and meaning because it is linked to Creation and the Creator. It is a day which brings a balanced perspective to life, an opportunity for man to be in communion with man and with God. In my view, however, as I read the Charter, it mandates that the legislative preservation of a Sunday day of rest should be secular, the diversity of belief and non-belief, the diverse socio-cultural backgrounds of Canadians make it constitutionally incompetent for the federal Parliament to provide legislative preference for any one religion at the expense of those of another religious persuasion”.
[102]The danger to constitutional analysis is that if you ask an artificial question you get an artificial answer.
[103]See Redlich et al Constitutional Law 3 ed (Matthew Bender, New York 1996) at 1527.
[104][1997] ZACC 5; 1997 (3) SA 1012 (CC); 1997 (6) BCLR 759 (CC).
[105]Id at paras 18–9.
[106]Id at para
20.
[107]Section 35(1) of the
Constitution provides:
“In interpreting the provisions of this Chapter a court of law shall promote the values which underlie an open and democratic society based on freedom and equality and shall, where applicable, have regard to public international law applicable to the protection of the rights entrenched in this Chapter, and may have regard to comparable foreign case law.”
[108]Prinsloo
v Van der Linde above n 10 at para
20.
[109]Section 33(1) of the
Constitution provides:
“The rights entrenched in this Chapter may be limited by law of general application, provided that such limitation –
(a) shall be permissible only to the extent that it is –
(i) reasonable; and
(ii) justifiable in an open and democratic society based on freedom and equality; and
(b) shall not negate the essential content of the right in question, and provided further that any limitation to –
(aa) a right entrenched in section 10, 11, 12, 14(1), 21, 25 or 30(1)(d) or (e) or (2); or
(bb) a right entrenched in section 15, 16, 17, 18, 23 or 24, in so far as such right relates to free and fair political activity,
shall, in addition to being reasonable as required in paragraph (a)(i), also be necessary.”
[110]This is underlined by Constitutional Principle XII in schedule 4 which required the Constitutional Assembly, when drafting the new Constitution to ensure that:
“Collective rights of self-determination in forming, joining and maintaining organs of civil society, including linguistic, cultural and religious associations, shall, on the basis of non-discrimination and free association, be recognised and protected.” (My emphasis)
[111]Du Plessis and Corder Understanding South Africa’s Transitional Bill of Rights (Juta & Co Ltd, Kenwyn 1994) at 157.
[112]See schedule 3 to the Constitution.
[113]See above n
15.
[114]See above n
13.
[115]West Virginia State
Board of Education v Barnette [1943] USSC 130; 319 US 624, 642 (1943) per Jackson J giving
the opinion of the
court.
[116]“This
Constitution provides a historic bridge between the past of a deeply divided
society characterised by strife, conflict,
untold suffering and injustice, and a
future founded on the recognition of human rights, democracy and peaceful
co-existence and
development opportunities for all South Africans, irrespective
of colour, race, class, belief or sex.
The pursuit of national unity, the well-being of all South African citizens and peace require reconciliation between the people of South Africa and the reconstruction of society.
The adoption of this Constitution lays the secure foundation for the people of South Africa to transcend the divisions and strife of the past, which generated gross violations of human rights, the transgression of humanitarian principles in violent conflicts and a legacy of hatred, fear, guilt and revenge.”
[117]See the
judgment of Dickson CJC in Big M above n 7 at 105 where he states that
what unites various principles and values “is the notion of the centrality
of individual
conscience and the inappropriateness of governmental intervention
to compel or to constrain its manifestation.”
[118]Van der Vyver “Religion” in Joubert The Law of South Africa vol 23 (Butterworths, Durban 1986) at 197.
[119]Id at
197.
[120]Id. See also Van der
Westhuizen “Freedom of Expression” in Van Wyk et al Rights and
Constitutionalism, The New South African Legal Order (Juta & Co Ltd,
Kenwyn 1994) 264 at 282:
“[South Africans] have been subjected to a system of censorship which was intended to impose the Calvinist morality of a small ruling establishment on the entire population.”
Also quoted in the judgment of Mokgoro J in Case and Another v Minister of Safety and Security and Others; Curtis v Minister of Safety and Security and Others [1996] ZACC 7; 1996 (3) SA 617 (CC); 1996 (5) BCLR 609 (CC) at para 11. See also Dlamini “Culture, Education, and Religion” in Van Wyk Rights and Constitutionalism 573 at 597:
“Although there has been no religious intolerance of Christianity in South Africa, the same cannot be said of other religions. Moreover, even when it comes to Christianity, the government in the past did not allow the free expression of Christian convictions. . . . Those who opposed [the] policies and practices [of apartheid] in the name of Christianity were ruthlessly suppressed.”
[121]In both instances the appropriate legislation provided that the religious convictions of the parents and the pupils should be respected in regard to religious instruction and religious ceremonies. Van der Vyver above n 24 at 197.
[122]Id at 199 and 198.
[123]“Dancing” was defined in section 1 of the Control of Dancing Ordinance 12 of 1957 (OFS) as “to dance with a partner to the accompaniment of music”. See also Van der Vyver above n 24 at 199.
[124]Above n 24 at 198.
[125]See schedule 1 to the Public Holidays Act 36 of 1994.
[126]See, generally, Sinclair The Law of Marriage vol 1 (Juta & Co Ltd, Kenwyn 1996) at 164–5.
[127]Seedat’s
Executors v The Master (Natal) 1917 AD 302 at 307 (per Innes CJ). See also
Ismail v Ismail 1983 (1) SA 1006 (A) at 1026; Kerr “Back to the
Problems of a Hundred or More Years Ago: Public Policy Concerning Contracts
Relating to Marriages
that are Potentially or Actually Polygamous” (1984)
101 South African Law Journal
445.
[128]In S Narayan (ed)
The Selected Works of Mahatma Gandhi: Satyagraha in South Africa vol 3
(Navajivan Publishing House, India 1928) at 377–8, M K Gandhi refers to
“the terrible judgment” in the Cape
Supreme Court setting aside the
practice of forty years, which
“. . . thus nullified in South Africa at a stroke of the pen all marriages celebrated according to the Hindu, Musalman and Zoroastrian rites. The many married Indian women in South Africa in terms of this judgement ceased to rank as the wives of their husbands and were degraded to the rank of concubines, while their progeny were deprived of their right to inherit the parents’ property. This was an insufferable situation for women no less than men, and the Indians in South Africa were deeply agitated”.
The shock to Indian women was so great that for the first time they joined in the Satyagraha campaign. Gandhi continued (at 388):
“It was an absolute pure sacrifice that was offered by these sisters, who were innocent of legal technicalities, and many of whom had no idea of country, their patriotism being based only upon faith. Some of them were illiterate and could not read the papers. But they knew that a mortal blow was being aimed at the Indians’ honour, and their going to jail was a cry of agony and prayer offered from the bottom of their heart, and was in fact the purest of all sacrifices.”
The “terrible judgment” is reported as Esop v Union Government (Minister of the Interior) 1913 CPD 133. Counsel for the government argued that “Mariam is in law the concubine and not the wife of the applicant.” (At 134). And Searle J said that “The courts of this country have always set their faces against recognition of these so-called Mahommedan marriages as legal unions”. (At 135).
See also Cachalia “Citizenship, Muslim family law and a future South African constitution: a preliminary enquiry” (1993) 56 THRHR 392 at 398–9.
[129]Ryland v
Edros 1997 (2) SA 690 (C) at 707G–H; 1997 (1) BCLR 77 (C) at
90F–G.
[130]In the
Ismail case above n 33 at 1025F–G, the Appellate Division held
that:
“. . . the [Islamic] customs and the contract in question are contrary to public policy and are, consequently, unenforceable.”
For the purposes of the present matter it is not necessary to express any views on whether polygyny as such would be contrary to public policy as developed in the light of the values of the Constitution. The present case does not require us to examine the extent to which section 14 gives constitutional protection to practices of a cultural or economic character which have a basis in or are associated with religious belief.
[131]Fraser v Children’s Court, Pretoria North and Others 1997 (2) SA 261 (CC); 1997 (2) BCLR 153 (CC) at para 21.
[132]Milton Shain The Roots of Anti-Semitism in South Africa (WUP, Johannesburg 1994) at 148 refers to the way in which anti-semitism moved from the private or ideational sphere into the public realm.
[133]Tribe American
Constitutional Law 2 ed (The Foundation Press Inc, Mineola 1988) at 1171
(footnote omitted).
[134]The
observations of Paul Sieghart bear quotation in full:
“Few of the major human religions have not at one time or another suffered persecution, or themselves persecuted – through the authority of a State in which they have become established – the members of other religions, or heretics within their own fold. For a substantial proportion of the worst atrocities perpetrated in recorded history, the ostensible justification has been the alleged need for the dominance or maintenance of one belief system rather than another. This is not the place to recite a catalogue of religious persecutions over the ages, let alone to describe the iniquities perpetrated either by, or against, any particular religious group. Suffice it to recall that the movement for ‘freedom of belief’ precedes every other in the history of the struggle for human rights and fundamental freedoms”.
The International Law of Human Rights (Clarendon Press, Oxford 1983) at 324.
[135]This issue has divided
judges in a number of North American cases. See, for example, Braunfeld
above n 4, Edwards Books and Art Ltd v The Queen (1986) 28 CRR 1, and
Jones v The Queen (1986) 25 CRR
63.
[136]See Nowak and Rotunda
Constitutional Law 5 ed (West Publishing Co, St Paul 1995) at 1315:
“To hold otherwise would be to require the state to pursue its goal of establishing a uniform day of rest by choosing a day when the least number of people might use the time to attend religious services.”
[137]See, for example, section 10(1)(a) of the Basic Conditions of Employment Act 3 of 1983.
[138]The French Revolutionary Calendar, described as “a splendid instrument for the protection of a national, republican religion against international Christianity”, lasted only from 1794 until 1804 when the Gregorian Calendar with its Saints’ Days and Church holidays was restored. See Gottschalk The Era of the French Revolution (1715–1815) (Houghton Mifflin Company, Cambridge 1957) at 259 and 341. The United Nations, containing member countries which officially recognise religions such as Buddhism, Islam and Judaism as constituting elements of their constitutional character, uses the internationally accepted calendar, though certain individual members do not. We could hardly be expected in South Africa to strike out the case number of the matter before us because the year 1997 is dated from the year given by Christians as that when Christ was born.
[139]If Christian origin alone were enough to establish unconstitutionality, then pictures of religious inspiration would have to be removed from public galleries, and the masses, cantatas and requiems originally composed for performance in a Cathedral could no longer be played in the City Hall; the province of Kwa-Zulu Natal would have to shed the second part of its name, and Port St Johns would also have to secularise itself; more fundamentally, it cannot be said that obedience by the criminal law to the Biblical Commandment “Thou shalt not kill” involves an invasion of section 14.
[140]Lynch above n 6 at 714–6. In reading this passage it should be noted that the US Establishment Clause is manifestly less accommodating to religion than is section 14 of the Constitution. Moreover, the difficulties of establishing bright lines in the area of religion and conscience are borne out by the fact that Brennan J and O’Connor J applied similar approaches in this case, but came to different conclusions, the former writing in dissent and favouring unconstitutionality of the display of the creche, the latter finding it not to be unconstitutional.
[141]See Certification of the Constitution of the Western Cape, 1997 (CC) Case No CCT 6/97, 2 September 1997, not yet reported, at para 28.
[142]Nor, for the same reason,
does it involve unfair discrimination on grounds of religion, conscience and
belief in terms of section
8(2). The issue of unfair discrimination on those
grounds was not fully argued before
us.
[143]See Tribe above n 39
at 1262:
“A more plausible dichotomy may be that between those government measures (1) that put an individual to a choice between adherence to religious duties and enjoyment of government benefits (or . . . avoidance of a government burden like criminal prosecution), and (2) those government measures that are not triggered by the religious choice in question but burden religious activity only in a manner ancillary to an undeniably secular choice.” (My emphasis)
[144]In Lee v Weisman [1992] USSC 104; 505 US 577, 594 (1992) Kennedy J stated:
“The injury caused by the government’s action . . . is that the State, in a school setting, in effect required participation in a religious exercise. . . . [T]he embarrassment and the intrusion of the religious exercise cannot be refuted by arguing that these prayers, and similar ones to be said in the future, are of a de minimis character.”
[145]As Jackson J in United States v Ballard 322 US 78, 92 and 94 (1944) remarked sardonically:
“. . . I do not see how we can separate an issue as to what is believed from considerations as to what is believable. . . . Religious symbolism is even used by some with the same mental reservations one has in teaching of Santa Claus or Uncle Sam or Easter bunnies or dispassionate judges.”
[146]See the judgment of Dickson CJC in Big M above n 7 at 99 where he adopts the following quotation of Professor Barron in “Sunday in North America” (1965) 79 Harvard Law Review 42, 53:
“The legislature may be able to divorce the secular Sunday from the religious Sunday of history, but the Orthodox Jew, the Seventh Day Adventist, and the atheist cannot.”
[147]Tribe above n 39 at 1205 suggests that O’Connor J in the Lynch case asked the right question, but gave the wrong answer because she approached the matter from the point of view of “the reasonable Christian”.
[148]See Wallace, Governor of Alabama v Jaffree; Smith v Jaffree 472 US 38, 76 (1985) where O’Connor J held in effect that something should be deemed sufficiently secular in aim if a fully informed, independent observer would judge it to have a predominantly secular purpose at the time it is challenged. See also Tribe above n 39 at 1205.
[149]Above n 35 SALR at 707G–H; BCLR at 90F–G.
[150]See section 33(1)(b)(aa) above n 15.
[151][1995] ZACC 6; 1995 (3) SA 632 (CC); 1995 (7) BCLR 861 (CC) at para 59.
[152]In Coetzee v Government of the Republic of South Africa; Matiso and Others v Commanding Officer, Port Elizabeth Prison, and Others [1995] ZACC 7; 1995 (4) SA 631 (CC); 1995 (10) BCLR 1382 (CC) at paras 55–60, I dealt extensively with the way the term “necessary” had been interpreted when used in international human rights instruments and came to the conclusion that the term “necessary” was not made the subject of rigid definition, but rather regarded as implying a series of interrelated elements in which central place was given to the proportionality of the means used to achieve a pressing and legitimate public purpose.
[153][1995] ZACC 3; 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC); 1995 (6) BCLR 665 (CC) at para 104.
[154][1997] ZACC 4; 1997 (6) BCLR 708 (CC) at para 41.
[155] (1989) 45 CRR 1 at 26–7.
[156]See S v Bhulwana; S v
Gwadiso [1995] ZACC 11; 1996 (1) SA 388 (CC); 1995 (12) BCLR 1579 (CC) at para 18 where
O’Regan J says: “The more substantial the inroad into fundamental
rights, the more persuasive the
grounds of justification must
be.”
[157]See Hogg
Constitutional Law of Canada 3 ed (Carswell, Scarborough 1992) at 861
where he says:
“The severity of the contravention [of a Charter right] would not be irrelevant, of course, because it would be harder to establish that a severe contravention was reasonable and demonstrably justified.”
[158]Compare Edwards Books above n 41 at 38 (competitive pressure on retailers to abandon the observance of a Saturday sabbath could not be characterised as insubstantial or trivial) and Jones above n 41 at 85 (legislative or administrative action whose effect on religion is trivial or insubstantial is not a breach of freedom of religion).
[159]Tribe above n 39 at 1224. See also Lynch above n 6.
[160]Above n 7 at 97–8.
[161]See Prinsloo above n 10 at para 20.
[162]See paragraph 90 of this judgment.
[163]See Kurland “The Religion Clauses and the Burger Court” (1984) 34 Cath ULR 1 at 13–4 quoted in Stone et al above n 2 at 1571.
[164]In this sense, the message
per se has far less religious tonality than does the nativity scene over which
the US Supreme Court divided
in Lynch above n
6.
[165]It would indeed be odd
if this Court could not take judicial notice of matters massively testified to
in criminal and family cases
which regularly come before the courts. Hoffmann J
in Stoke-on-Trent City Council v B & Q Plc; Norwich City Council v B
& Q Plc (1991) ChD 48 at 65 (which concerned balancing out respect for
store-closing on the “English Sunday” against the principle of
unrestricted
trade everywhere in the European Union) deals with judicial notice
in the following terms:
“[I]f the court is satisfied on the basis of judicial notice that the requirements of proportionality have been met, there is no need for the prosecution to adduce oral or documentary evidence. Judicial notice is not confined to questions which everyone would be able to answer of his own knowledge. It includes matters of a public nature such as history, social customs and public opinion which may have to be culled from works of reference. As the late Professor Sir Rupert Cross said in Cross on Evidence 5th ed. (1979), p. 160, judicial notice is important for two reasons:
‘In the first place, it expedites the hearing of many cases. Much time would be wasted if every fact which was not admitted had to be the subject of evidence which would, in many cases, be costly and difficult to obtain. Secondly, the doctrine tends to produce uniformity of decision on matters of fact where a diversity of findings might sometimes be distinctly embarrassing’.”
Similar points are made by Hogg above n 63 at 858–9 where he says that it would be unfortunate if a law was struck down because of a deficiency in the evidence which could be supplied by a common sense finding. After dealing with the problems of costs involved in parading experts, he offers the opinion that:
“it would be desirable for Charter review to become less dependent on evidence, even if the courts have to strain somewhat to make ‘obvious’ or ‘self-evident’ findings.”
[166]Rejecting the argument that the absence of an establishment clause in the Canadian Charter meant that a Canadian court should not adopt principles relating to religious freedom developed in the United States of America, Dickson CJC said that: “[t]he theological content of the legislation remains as a subtle and constant reminder to religious minorities within the country of their differences with, and alienation from, the dominant religious culture.” Big M above n 7 at 98 and 99–101.